1. The Liar 说谎者悖论 英文解析 逻辑学教材

1. The Liar  说谎者悖论 英文解析  逻辑学教材
1. The Liar  说谎者悖论 英文解析  逻辑学教材

The Paradoxes of Eubulides of Miletus (4th century B.C.)

1. The Liar

“When I lie and admit that I lie, do I lie or speak the truth?”1

I . The Paradox

A statement that directly or indirectly predicates falsehood of itself is logically

pathological in the worst, most mind-boggling way. Such sentences are called …liar sentences .? Version 1a : This sentence is false.

Proof of Paradoxicality

-That sentence, like every other, must be either true or false.

-If the sentence is true, then it follows that what it says is the case. It says that it is false, and, since what it says is the case, it therefore is false. So, if the sentence is true, then it follows that it is false. Contradiction .

-Therefore (by reductio ad absurdum /~I), the sentence …This sentence is false? cannot be true and, so, must be false.

-But if the proposition is false, then it follows that what it says is not the case. It says that it is false, and, as what it says is not the case, it follows that it is not the case that it is false. Therefore, the sentence is true. So, if the sentence is false, then it follows that it is true. Contradiction .

-Therefore (by reductio ad absurdum ), the sentence …This sentence is false? cannot be false and, so, must be true, which (as we proved) it cannot be…???!!!

As the argument shows, a proposition that directly or indirectly says of itself that it is false must be either true of false (like any other proposition), and, pathologically, cannot be either.

Version 1b : I am lying.

Version 2a : The following sentence is false.

The preceding sentence is true.

1 Aulus Gellius, Attic Nights , vol. 3, bk. XVIII, ch. II. Version 2b :

Hmwk . 1. Show in full and precise detail (on the model of my previous demonstration)

that these three situations are genuinely paradoxical, i.e., some statement must be false if it is true, must be true if it is false, and no third option is

possible.

In all four variations, the truth of a sentence directly or indirectly implies its own falsehood (which is a contradiction), and the sentence?s falsity directly or indirectly implies its own truth (which is a contradiction). By itself, one of these contradictory results merely would constitute a valid reductio ad absurdum/indirect proof for the non-contradictory denial of the assumption (of either truth or falsehood). But, both contradictory results together generate ineliminable contradictoriness: we must hold as true what we cannot hold as true…and the mind boggles. (Such paradoxes are also called …antinomies.?)

II. In the New Testament

In his Epistle to Titus, the Apostle Paul complains of the Cretans adding:2

One of themselves, even a prophet of their own, said, …The Cretans are always liars, evil beasts, slow bellies.? This witness is true.

According to St. Paul, then, there is a Cretan prophet who asserts that the Cretans always lie, which implies, of course, that the Cretan prophet himself is lying.3Now, that?s fine; but in adding that the Cretan prophet is telling the truth, Paul brutely contradicted himself.

Proof

1. Epimenides is a Cretan.

2. Epimenides said, “The Cretans are always liars.”

*3. This witness is true, i.e., what Epimenides said is true.

4. Therefore, “The Cretans are always liars” is true. [by (2) & (3)]

5. Therefore, the Cretans are always liars. [by (4)]

6. Therefore, Epimenides always lies. [by (1) & (5)]

7. Therefore, Epimenides lied when he said, “The Cretans are always liars.” [by (6)]

8. Therefore, what Epimenides said is false, i.e., this witness is false. [by (7)]

Contradiction: (3) & (8)! St. Paul?s assertion that Epi menides told the truth

implies that Epimenides lied.

Though the Apostle seems not to have realized it, we know that his self-contradiction constitutes a valid reductio ad absurdum (or is it a consequentia mirabilis?) that (3)—his assertion that the witness is true—is false.

Have we just disproven the thesis of Biblical literalism—every statement in the Bible is

literally true?

2 Titus 1: 12-13. The mentioned Cretan prophet was probably Epimenides, and the Liar Paradox is often called the Epimenidean Paradox.

3By the way, a Cretan is a person from Crete while a cretin is an idiot. You?re bound to insult somebody if you mix the two words up, so get it straight. (Originally, a cretin was someone who suffered the crippling mental and physical results of thyroid disease. The word …cretin? comes from the Swiss French …crestin’ meaning …Christian.? That is, these unfortunates, though retarded and deformed, are still human beings.)

It then follows that the witness is false, i.e., what Epimenides said is false. However, this conclusion does not entail a contradiction.To see that, let?s find out what that conclusion does entail.

Argument

a. The witness is false, i.e., what Epimenides said is false. [by Proof]

b. Epimenides said, “The Cretans are always liars.” [by (2)]

c. Therefore, …The Cretans are always liars? is false. [by (a) & (b)]

d. Therefore, …Some Cretans are not always liars? is tru

e.

Proof: The contradictory of an A proposition is the corresponding O proposition. Or, in

the language of predicate logic, ~(?x)(…x…) is equivalent to (?x)~(…x…) (by the

quantifier negation rule).

e. Therefore, there is at least one Cretan who does not always lie, i.e., who tells the truth

on at least one occasion.

[by (d)] f. There are three ways for (e) to be true:

i. Epimenides told the truth on this occasion,

ii. He told the truth on at least one other occasion, or

iii. There is at least one other Cretan who sometimes tells the truth.

Argument: I can?t think of any other.

g. (i) is false. [by (a)]

h. We have no grounds for denying either (ii) or (iii).

Argument: The fact that Epimenides lied on the relevant occasion alone implies nothing about the truthfulness of his other assertions or other Cretans? assertions.

i. Therefore, either (ii) or (iii) (or both) is true.

So, it follows from Epimenides? having spoken falsely when he said that the Cretans are always liars that at least one Cretan spoke, or will speak, truly on at least one occasion. And there is certainly nothing contradictory about that. In fact, I?m sure it?s true (and you are too).

If the only thing any Cretan ever had said, or ever would say, were, “The Cretans are

always liars,” then we?d be in trouble; but since that isn?t the case, we?re not.

Thus, Paul?s blunder isn?t genuinely paradoxical. So, it?s not really a version of the Liar, but I include it for its historical and religious interest.4

III. Reductio ad Absurdum?

4I can?t resist giving one more fascinating version of the liar paradox due to medieval logicians. So, for the sake of argument let?s accept the medieval claim that …God exists? i s necessarily true. Consider the following argument: God exists. Therefore, this argument is invalid. Is the argument valid? (Any necessarily true proposition may replace …God exists.?)

It?s worth being clear that there is no reductio ad absurdum escape from the Liar. For, what unrecognized, implicit assumption have we made such that we can take the Liar?s double-contradictory conclusion to constitute a reductio ad absurdum proof for its falsehood? Well, to begin, we?ve assumed that there is a liar sentence. So, perhaps the Liar proves there

is no such sentence. No, this is ridiculous! We didn?t assume that a liar sentence exists. The sentence is right there on page 1! (You don?t ne ed to turn back; the rumored-to-be-non-existent sentence will occur in my next sentence.)

We?ve also implicitly assumed that the sentence, …This sentence is false? actually says something, i.e., that the sentence is meaningful, it expresses a proposition. Maybe the Liar proves that that is a perfectly grammatical sentence that expresses no proposition, is meaningless.5 This suggestion fails for two reasons.

First Reason.If the sentence …This sentence is false? expresses no proposition, then it follows that it is meaningless. Therefore, that sentence is neither true nor false, and, so, we seem to have escaped. But, consider the sentence:

This sentence is not true.

This new sentence is also a paradoxical liar sentence.

Hmwk. 2. Prove it.

Now, according to the proposed solution, the new sentence is also meaningless, and, therefore, neither true nor false, and, thus, not true. But, the new sentence just says that it is not true. Therefore, it is true (for what it says is the case)! But if the sentence is true, then it cannot be meaningless. Consequently, the proposal does not resolve the paradox.

Second Reason. The proposal only ever had a chance of resolving versions 1a & 1b in which a sentence directly predicated falsehood of itself. In versions 2a & 2b, where a sentence indirectly predicates falsehood to itself by ascribing a truth-value to another sentence, it?s clear that the sentence is perfectly meaningful because you effortlessly understood it. After all, it was only as a result of reading it that you went on to consider precisely the sentence to which it referred.

Perhaps another example shows the point even more clearly:

The sentence printed in the box on p. 160 of Howard DeLong’s A Profile of

Mathematical Logic (Addison-Wesley, 1970) is true.

Go ahead; look it up. (I?ll wait.)

Finally, we?ve implicitly assumed the principle of bivalence: (i) there are only two truth-values, viz., the true and the false, and (ii) every sentence must have one, and only one,

of these. Therefore, we?ve implicitly assumed that our liar sentences have to be either true or false. Perhaps the Liar shows that some meaningful sentences have no truth-value. This is a

5 The Stoic logician Chrysippus suggested this resolution.

very complex and abstract reply, too complex and abstract for us to give it much consideration now.6 However, we can at least consider how difficult it is to make sense of the possibility that a sentence expresses something coherent about the way things are and, yet, it is neither true nor false, i.e., things neither are that way nor not that way. Which way, then are things supposed to be?

It seems, then, that the Liar, unlike the Barber or the Law Court, is a genuine paradox. IV. What the Liar Paradox Shows

Like questions about Russell?s barber shaving himself, the Liar reveals the surprising paradoxicality that self-reference sometimes produces. Now, self-reference clearly is not paradoxical in general, for most instances of it are perfectly coherent. Consider some examples.

1. Sax self-referentially asserts tha t he is bald. His statement is simply false, but it isn?t

paradoxical. (Indeed, a statement must be coherent even to be false.)

2. (i)-(iv) of the following self-referential sentences are just true; (v)-(vi) are just false:7

i. This sentence contains five words.

ii. This sentence contains thirty-six letters.

iii. There are fourteen vowels in this sentence.

iv. This sentence is written in English.

v. This sentence contains precisely fifty characters.

vi. Deis ist kein Deutscher Satz. [Translation: This sentence is not in German.]

3. Epimenides can self-referentially assert the self-referential sentence, “The sentence I am now

uttering contains nine words,” and his remark will be unproblematically true.

Still, the Liar shows that those instances of self-reference in which a statement directly or indirectly predicates falsehood of itself are logically pathological in the worst, most mind-boggling way: they generate ineliminable, unresolvable contradiction. And, the Liar also shows that a liar sentence can be constructed in any language with the resources to:

A. refer to its own sentences, and

B. predicate truth or falsity of those sentences.

Unhappily, all natural languages (like Gujarati, Magyar, Frisian, etc.) satisfy (A) and (B). That is very bad, for, as we?ve seen, liar sentences generate unpreventable contradiction, and, as we?ve learned, every statement validly follows and is derivable from a contradiction. In such a language, therefore, the entire practice of deductive reasoning as part of the search for truth is hopelessly corrupt. So, deductive rationality carried on in English (Basque, Korean, etc.) is a farce and a delusion…unless we can escape from the Liar.

6 But, see the handout “Deviant Logic, No. 3: Bo?var?s 3-Valued Logic.”

7A sentence like these that describes its own content or construction is called an …autogram.?

V.A Proposed Solution

One way to escape would be to somehow guarantee that liar sentences could never arise.8 In 1931, the logician Alfred Tarski argued that we could block the possibility of liar sentences if we:9

1. strictly distinguish object languages from metalanguages, and

2. restrict language so that it is only in the metalanguage that one can construct sentences about the sentences of an object language, and, so, predicate truth or falsity of those

object-language sentences.

Satisfying these conditions would prevent a language from doing (A) and (B).

For example, the English language would become an infinite sequence of distinct languages: English1, English2, English3, …where each succeeding language would be the meta-language for the previous one.

English1 would contain almost all of the vocabulary of the English we currently speak, but it would lack all semantic vocabulary: words like …sentence,? …proposition,? …assertion,? …meaning,? …lies,? …true,? etc. Thus, we could talk abo ut snow (and shoes, ships, and sealing wax, etc.) in English1 by asserting the English1sentence, …Snow is white.? However, English1 would lack the resources for us to be able to talk about any English1 sentences (or any other sentences) in English1.

So, if we would want to talk about the English1sentence …Snow is white? in order to say, for example, that it is true, then we would have to treat English1 as the object language and speak in its metalanguage English2. Among its vocabulary, English2 has the semantic terms needed to talk about sentences in English1. Only in English2, then, could we say that …Snow is white? is true, which we would do by asserting the English2sentence, “The English1sentence …Snow is white? is true.”

Now, English2 only has the semantic vocabulary needed to talk about sentences in English1, not its own sentences (or those of any other language in the sequence). Similarly, then, it would be only in English3—the metalanguage of English2—that we could construct a sentence to assert the truth of that English2 sentence, viz. “The English2sentence, …The English1sentence, “Snow is white” is true? is true.” And so on through the series of English metalanguages.

As no language in the infinite series could satisfy either (A) or (B), Tarski?s stratification banishes all same-level sentence reference and, thus, all sentence self-reference, 8 Of course, banishing all self-reference would guarantee that. But, that program would be ridiculously extreme. Almost all instances of self-reference are harmless and, indeed, very useful if not practically irreplaceable.

9In “The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages,” but for a very readable version I recommend Tarski?s “Truth and Proof” [Scientific American, vol. 194, no. 6, pp. 63-77].

as ungrammatical and, therefore, meaningless. Consequently, no sentence in any of the languages could directly say anything at all about itself.

Hmwk. 3. Prove that version 1a of the Liar cannot be constructed in Tarski?s hierarchy.

Of course, one could utter or write the words …This sentence is false? or …I am lying,? but these putative self-referential constructions would be utterly ungrammatical—like the English construction …Shoes pointedly my sleep eat?—and, hence, not sentences; therefore, not meaningful; and, so, without truth-values.

Equally, indirectly self-referring sentences would be impossible to construct.

Hmwk. 4. Prove that version 2a of the Liar cannot be constructed in Tarski?s hierarchy.

Therefore, no sentence in any language in the series could (directly or indirectly) predicate falsity of itself. Consequently, no liar sentence could be constructed in any language in the series, and the paradox would be resolved.

Despite the fact that Tarski?s proposal would, if carried out, quash the liar paradox, the proposal has few adherents. (Yet, it?s impossible to overstate the historical importance o f Tarski?s work.) The problem is that Tarski?s proposal is too crude, for it banishes not only liar sentences but all (directly or indirectly) self-referring sentences. Consequently, it is too extreme, for, again, the vast majority of self-referring sentences are perfectly banal, and some are practically irreplaceable—consider the indirectly self-referring sentence, …All English sentences begin with a capital letter.? There is no good reason to proscribe all of these sentences and very good reasons not to proscribe some of them.

It is also interesting to note that successfully carrying out Tarski?s proposal makes that proposal impossible. If Tarski?s stratification were carried out, the description of the hierarchy of languages would have to be impossible, for the sentences of that description would have to belong to some finite level of the hierarchy in order to be meaningful, but in order to describe the whole hierarchy they couldn?t belong to any of its levels.

英文诗歌赏析

英文诗歌赏析安全B103班 峥 201010044323

Anaiysis on the poem of------ The most distant way in the world Poet:Tagore The most distant way in the world is not the way from birth to the end. It is when I sit near you that you don’t understand I lov e you. The most distant way in the world is not that you’re not sure I love you. It is when my love is bewildering the soul but I can’t speak it out The most distant way in the world is not that I can’t say I love you. It is after looking into my heart I can’t change my love. The most distant way in the world is not that I’m loving you. It is in our love we are keeping between the distance. The most distant way inthe world is not the distance across us. It is when we’re breaking through the way we deny the existance of love. So the most distant way in the world is not in two distant trees. It is the same rooted branches can’t enjoy the co-existance. So the most distant way in the world is not in the being sepearated branches. It is in the blinking stars they can’t burn the light.

英语教案格式模板范文

英语教案格式模板范文

英语教案格式模板范文 【篇一:全英文英语教案模板】 lesson plan nsefc module2 unit reading in teacher: period:period1 type:reading duration: 45minutes teaching ideology the current theory view reading as a interactive process which involves not only the printed page but also the reader’s old knowledge of the language in general, the world and the text types. in the reading process, these factors interact with each other and compensate for each other. based on the understanding of reading as an interactive process, teaching reading in the classroom is divided into three stages in which the top-down and bottom-up techniques integrated to develop the students language efficiency in general and reading strategies. the three stages are pre-reading, while-reading and post-reading. teaching material and learning condition the analysis of teaching material the teaching material is the reading part from nsefc module2 unit. the topic of this unit is . this passage mainly introduces the passage consists of paragraphs. the first paragraph is a general introduction of the . para.2 to para.4 introduces . the last paragraph tells about . the topic is not new to the ss. but there is some new words and phases in the passage. the analysis of learning condition

sonnet 18 莎士比亚的作品《第十八行诗》赏析 英文版

The speaker of the poem opens with a question that is addressed to the beloved, "Shall I compare thee to a summer's day?" This question is comparing her to the summer time of the year. It is during this time when the flowers are blooming, trees are full of leaves, the weather is warm, and it is generally thought of as an enjoyable time during the year. The following eleven lines in the poem are also dedicated to similar comparisons between the beloved and summer days. In lines 2 and 3, the speaker explains what mainly separates the young woman from the summer's day: she is "more lovely and more temperate." (Line 2) Summer's days tend toward extremes: they are sometimes shaken by "rough winds" (line3) which happens and is not always as welcoming as the woman. However in line 4, the speaker gives the feeling again that the summer months are often to short by saying, "And summer抯lease hath too short a date." In the summer days, the sun, "the eye of heaven" (line 5), often shines "too hot," or too dim, "his gold complexion dimmed" (line 6), that is there are many hot days during the summer but soon the sun begins to set earlier at night because autumn is approaching. Summer is moving along too quickly for the speaker, its time here needs to be longer, and it also means that the chilling of autumn is coming upon us because the flowers will soon be withering, as "every fair from fair sometime declines." (Line 7) The final portion of the sonnet tells how the beloved differs from the summer in various respects. Her beauty will be one that lasts forever, "Thy eternal summer shall not fade." (Line 9), and never end or die. In the couplet at the bottom, the speaker explains how that the beloved's beauty will accomplish this everlasting life unlike a summer. And it is because her beauty is kept alive in this poem, which will last forever. It will live "as long as men can breathe or eyes can see." (Line 13)On the surface, the poem is on the surface simply a statement of praise about the beauty of the beloved woman and perhaps summer to the speaker is sometimes too unpleasant with the extremes of windiness and heat that go along with it. However, the beloved in the poem is always mild and temperate by her nature and nothing at all like the summer. It is incidentally brought to life as being described as the "eye of heaven" with its "gold complexion". The imagery throughout the sonnet is simple and attainable to the reader, which is a key factor in understanding the poem. Then the speaker begins to describe the summer again with the "darling buds of May" giving way to the " summer’s lease", springtime moving into the warmth of the summer. The speaker then starts to promise to talk about this beloved, that is so great and awing that she is to live forever in this sonnet. The beloved is so great that the speaker will even go as far as to say that, "So long as men breathe, or eyes can see," the woman will live. The language is almost too simple when comparing it to the rest of Shakespeare’s sonnets; it is not heavy with alliteration or verse, and nearly every line is its own self-contained clause, almost every line ends with some punctuation that effects a pause. But it is this that makes Sonnet18 stand out for the rest in the book. It is much more attainable to understand and it allows for the reader to fully understand how great this beloved truly is because she may live forever in it. An important theme of the sonnet, as it is an important theme throughout much of the poetry in general, is the power of the speaker's poem to defy time and last forever. And so by doing this it is then carrying the beauty of the beloved down to future generations and eventually

如何分析英语诗歌

How to Analyze a Poem Going through each poem asking the following questions in an order something like this: 1.Who is the speaker? Is the speaker a male or female? Where is he or she? When does this poem take place? What are the circumstances? Sometimes you'll be able to answer all of these questions: For example, the speaker is a Duke, (eg My last Duchess). Sometimes you'll be able to answer only a few, and sometimes only vaguely: The speaker is unnamed, unplaced, and is addressing an audience that's unknown. No matter. You've begun to understand the poem. 2.What is the structure of the poem? That is, what are the parts of the poem and how are they related to each other? What gives the poem its coherence? What are the structural divisions of the poem? Think about the logic of the poem. Does it ask questions, then answer them? Or develop an argument? Or use a series of analogies to prove a point?

经典英文诗歌赏析(全)

经典英文诗歌赏析(全) 一 nothing gold can stay 1简介:《美景易逝(Nothing Gold Can Stay)》罗伯特弗罗斯特 的代表作之一。此诗于1923年写就,即于当年十月在《耶鲁杂志(The Yale Review)》上刊印出版,随后就被收录到弗罗斯特的一本名为 《新罕布什尔州(New Hampshire)》的诗集中。 2诗歌翻译: Nothing gold can stay 岁月留金 Nature's first green is gold, 大自然的第一抹新绿是金, Her hardest hue to hold. 也是她最无力保留的颜色.。 Her early leaf's a flower; 她初发的叶子如同一朵花,; But only so an hour. 不过只能持续若此一刹那。 Then leaf subsides leaf, 随之如花新叶沦落为旧叶。 So Eden sank to grief. 由是伊甸园陷入忧伤悲切, So down gose down to day, 破晓黎明延续至晃晃白昼。 Nothing gold can stay. 宝贵如金之物岁月难保留。 3诗歌赏析:这首诗揭示了一切真切而美好的事物最终定会逐渐消失的哲理。它同时也使用了独特的技巧来表现了季节的变化。想到了 小时了了,大未必佳。一切都是转瞬即逝的,浮世有的仅仅转丸般的 繁华。 二 the road not taken 1诗歌简介:这首名诗《The Road NotTaken》形式是传统的抑扬 格四音步,但音步可变(含有很多抑抑扬的成分);每节的韵式为abaab 。

莎士比亚十四行诗第十八首赏析

莎士比亚十四行诗第十八首赏析 摘要:莎士比亚是英国文学史上泰斗级人物。他创作的的154首十四行一向为时人推崇。十四行诗达到了登峰造极的程度,成为英诗史上璀璨的明珠。这理所要赏析的是莎翁十四行诗的第十八首,其热烈的情怀,精致的措辞和美妙的比喻,,不知令多少学者和诗人叹服,赏析文字者莫不称颂其妙。 关键词:莎士比亚十四行诗第18首 诗人一开头就把他的爱友比作美好的“夏天”,其中“夏天”一词颇有争论,很多学者认为应该翻译成春天,但以我个人的观点,还是应该译成夏天。因为英国的夏天相当于我国的春天或春末夏初,这是一年中最美好的季节,风和日暖,枝头绿叶冒新芽,百花含苞待开放,大地充满一派生机活力,迷人可爱。开篇第一句便直入主题,用一问一答得方式毫不含蓄的点名她的美。虽然夏天如此美丽,但仍然不及她之美。作者意不在提出疑问,而是通过疑问句,引出第二句肯定的回答,恰如其分地达到赞赏的目的,诗人如此煞费,说明她的美丽不仅令他赞赏,而且还令他崇敬。这比开篇便用一陈述句更有说服力。 接着第3456句,诗人进一步解释为什么“你比它可爱也比它温婉”,那是因为“狂风”会把“五月的嫩芽摧残”,“夏天的期限”太过于短暂,阳光过于“强烈”,有时却也会被“遮掩”。这一系列的意象,为我们勾勒出一副副夏景图,引人遐想。其中不难看出,作者对这一副副图景产生的是一种怜惜之情,这时让我们不禁思考,那诗人对她的怜爱,该有多么深沉。 后接着的两句:“世上娇艳之物都会凋零,受机缘或大自然的局限”,为我们阐释这样一个哲理:世界上所有美丽的事物都会有遵循着大自然的规律,随着时间的流逝而消失。这虽为一个众所周知的事实,却令古今多少文人墨客所感叹。 接着,诗人用一个转折,说“你的长夏永远不会消逝,永不会失去迷人的光彩;不会在死神阴影中漂泊”这的用暗喻的手法,将她的美丽比作“长夏”,意为有夏天的美丽,而且比夏天更长,有取夏天之长,补夏天之短的意味。后面接着补充,他的美丽不会时间而失去光泽,永远留存。 “这诗将与你同在,只要人活着,眼睛还能看。这诗将永存,赋予你生命。”到最后,诗人转向写诗歌,说诗歌是永存的。从这里我们不难看出,诗人内心是矛盾的,他大肆笔墨去描写他的美,去高歌他的美是永存的,事实上他只是在欺骗他自己,他深知“世上娇艳之物都会凋零,受机缘或大自然的局限”,当然他的美丽也属于“世上娇艳之物”,可是诗人不愿意承认,他无法说服他自己去接受这个事实,于是他想把他的美丽长存于他的心中,但是每个人都会到死神那里报到,怎么办呢?这时,他知道了,永存的,只有诗歌,他只有将他的美丽写入诗歌,才能永恒。 本诗的主题思想为:爱和美。这首诗以夏天的意象展开了想象,我们的脑海会立即浮现出绿荫的繁茂,娇蕾的艳丽。夏日既表示诗人的友人可爱,让人感到可意,又暗指他的友人正处于年轻、精力旺盛的时期,因为夏天总是充满了生机和活力。万物在春季复苏,夏天旺盛,所以夏天是生命最旺盛的季节,诗歌前六句,诗人歌颂了诗中的主人公“你”作为美的存在,却把“夏天”、“娇蕾”和“烈日”都比下去,因为它们不够“温婉”、“太短暂”、“会被遮暗”,所以“你”的魅力远远胜于夏天。第七和第八两句指出每一种美都会转瞬即逝,禁不住风吹雨打,而第九句到第十二句指出“你”的美将永驻,连死神都望而却步,与时间同长的美才是永恒的美。因为“你”在诗歌中永恒,千百年来天地间只要有诗歌艺术的存在,诗歌和“你”就能够永生。所以“你”的美永不枯凋,这是一种生命的美,艺术的美,永驻人间。 这首诗语言优美,不仅体现在用词的精确上,而且还体现在表达方法的多变上,

关于经典英文诗歌赏析

英语诗歌以其独特的文体形式充分调动、发挥语言的各种潜能,使之具有特殊的感染力。读来隽永,富有音韵美。下面是是由带来的关于经典英文诗歌,欢迎阅读! 【篇一】关于经典英文诗歌赏析 I Started Early - Took My Dog Emily Dickinson (1830-86) I started Early - Took my Dog And visited the Sea The Mermaids in the Basement Came out to look at me And Frigates - in the Upper Floor Extended Hempen Hands Presuming Me to be a Mouse Aground - upon the Sands But no Man moved Me - till the Tide Went past my simple Shoe And past my Apron - and my Belt And past my Bodice - too And made as He would eat me up As wholly as a Dew Upon a Dandelion's Sleeve And then - I started - too And He - He followed - close behind I felt His Silver Heel Upon my Ankle - Then my Shoes

Would overflow with Pearl Until We met the Solid Town No One He seemed to know And bowing - with a Mighty look At me - The Sea withdrew 【篇二】关于经典英文诗歌赏析 The Wild Swans At Coole William Butler Yeats (1865-1939) The trees are in their autumn beauty, The woodland paths are dry, Under the October twilight the water Mirror a still sky; Upon the brimming water among the stones Are nine-and-fifty swans. The nineteenth autumn has come upon me Since I first made my count; I saw, before I had well finished, All suddenly mount And scatter wheeling in great broken rings Upon their clamorous wings. I have looked upon those brilliant creatures, And now my heart is sore. All's changed since I, hearing at twilight, The first time on this shore,

最新英语教案模板3篇

最新英语教案模板3篇 教案是教师为顺利而有效地开展教学活动,根据课程标准,教学大纲和教科书要求及学生的实际情况,以课时或课题为单位,对教学内容、教学步骤、教学方法等进行的具体设计和安排的一种实用性教学文书.下面是小编为大家收集的,希望你们能喜欢 英语教案模板一 教学□标: 1、技能与知识目标 (1)能听懂并会说、会读Good afternoon.和What s your name? I m x x.的句型. (2)能听懂并会说、会读词汇your, name, afternoon. 2、运用能力H标 能在不同时间段,正确地向他人问好.(上午:Good morning!下午:Good afternoon!)能用What s your name?来询问他人姓名.通过歌曲的学习培养孩子的乐感与美感,增强学科间的融合. 教学重点: 能听懂并会说会读Good afternoon! What s your name? I m 及词汇your , name, afternoon. 教学难点: name中的/m/与afternoon中/n/的发音. 教学过程: —、Warm up 1、运用所学问候语进行师生间,生生间对话练习.Good morning! I m How are you? I m fine. And how are you? I m fine , too. Thank you. 2、同学们今天表现不错,那我们一起来做个游戏吧.活动帮助学生分清boys与 girls的用法.速度曲慢到快,指令可交替进行. 二、Lead in OK!boys and girls , you ve done a good job. Look!老师左右手各持一手偶, 通过变换音调来演一段对话,引出本课重点:What s your name ?手偶l:Hi, I m Mr. Li . What s your name?手偶2: Hello, I m Sam.

莎士比亚sonnet18 原创赏析

李政颖13麻醉二班110520130082 When I first read this poem in our class,I feel strange that not only for it’s some grammers I have even seen but also the feeling of the poet can not be touched by me.However when the teacher sounded about this sonnet and played the video that someone declaimed it,I felt something choicest and miraculous that I have not had in my heart. In the first of this poem,it take “you”compare with summer,incredible,I can not image that how a human have a commonality with it.But I am wrong.We know that when the nature is in summer,the world is all around green that everything grow to thrive and luxuriant tree cover the sunshine,it is the best time of the nature life.The green and the colorful,the sun and the shelter make summer so beautiful that it is believed as a marvel.Nevertheless, “you” are “more lovely and more temperate” that “rough wins do shake”the scene, the period of summer is “all too hot a date”and sometime too hot due to the heaven shines.The miraculous marvel can not put the same level with “you”.If you want to write such a sentence you must have a strong imagination. And “every fair from fair sometimes declines”, “by chance or nature’s changing ourse untrimmed”.(That is said the summer’s beauty that can not compare with yours).But “you”can overcome these disadvantages.your “eternal summer shall not fade”and your honor will be everlasting.Your are immortal, “nor shall death brag thou wand’rest in his shade,you are not going to die.You will get ensuring life in the poem while generation people is dying.You are live in the poetry described by the author,you exist in the poet’s heart also in ours though this expressive way,poem.----or you are the spirit of the poetry,you are the soul of human being. With this the poet is able to accomplish what many have done in poetry and that is to give the gift of an eternal life to someone that they believe is special and outshines everyone else around them. Perhaps it is because of a physical beauty that the speaker see, but I believe that it is more because of the internal beauty as seen in line 2,

英文诗歌赏析方法

英文诗歌赏析方法 英诗的欣赏:诗的格律、诗的押韵、诗的体式、诗的评判。 诗以高度凝结的语言表达着人们的喜怒哀乐,用其特有的节奏与方式影响着人们的精神世界。诗讲究联想,运用象征、比喻、拟人等各种修辞手法,形成了独特的语言艺术。 一、诗的格律 “格律是指可以用脚打拍子的节奏”,是每个音步轻重音节排列的格式,也是朗读时轻重音的依据。而音步是由重读音节和非重读音节构成的诗的分析单位。重读音节为扬(重),在音节上用“-”或“?”标示,非重读音节为抑(轻),在音节上用“?”标示,音步之间可用“/”隔开。以下是五种常见格式: 1. 抑扬格(轻重格)Iambus:是最常见的一种格式,每个音步由一个非重读音节加一个重读音节构成。 As fair / art thou / my bon/nie lass, So deep / in luve / am I : And I / will luve / thee still,/ my dear,Till a` / the seas / gang dry: Robert Burns(1759-1796):My Luve Is like a Red,Red Rose 注;art=are luve=love bonnie=beautiful a`=all gang=go 上例中为四音步与三音步交叉,可标示为:?-/?-/?-/(?-) 2.扬抑格(重轻格)Trochee:每个音步由一个重读音节加一个非重读音节构成。 下例中为四音步扬抑格(少一个轻音节),可标示为:-?/-?/-?/- Tyger!/ Tyger!/ burning / bright In the / forests / of the / night William Blake:The Tyger 3. 抑抑扬格(轻轻重格)Anapaestic foot:每个音步由两个非重读音节加一个重读音节构成。如:三音步抑抑扬格??-/??-/??- Like a child / from the womb, Like a ghost / from the tomb, I arise / and unbuild / it again. 4. 扬抑抑格(重轻轻格)Dactylic foot:每个音步由一个重读音节加两个非重读音节构成。如:两音步扬抑抑格-??/-?? ?Touch her not / ?scornfully, ?Think of her / ?mournfully. - Thomas Hood 5. 抑扬抑格(轻重轻格)Amphibrach:每个音步由一个非重读音节加一个重读音节再加一个非重读音节构成。如:三音步抑扬抑格?-?/?-?/?-?下例中最后一个音步为抑扬格。 O ?hush thee / my ?babie / thy ?sire was / a knight. 在同一首诗中常会出现不同的格律,格律解析对朗读诗歌有一定参考价值。现代诗中常不遵守规范的格律。 二、诗的押韵

英文诗歌赏析翻译

《英语诗歌欣赏》课程教学诗选 Types of Poetry Unit one Nature The Pasture Robert Frost (1874–1963) I’M going out to clean the pasture spring; I’ll only stop to rake the leaves away (And wait to watch the water clear, I may): I shan’t be gone long.—You come too. I’m going out to fetch the little calf That’s standing by the mother. It’s so young, It totters when she licks it with her tongue. I shan’t be gone long.—You come too. 牧场 罗伯特·弗罗斯特 (1874–1963) 我去清一清牧场的泉水, 我只停下来把落叶全耙去 (还瞧着泉水变得明净—也许); 我不会去得太久。—你也来吧。 我去把那幼小的牛犊抱来, 它站在母牛身边,小得可怜,一摇一晃,当母牛给她舔舔;我不会去得太久。—你也来吧。 (方平译) Daffodils William Wordsworth (1770-1850) I wondered lonely as a cloud That floats on high o'er vales and hills, When all at once I saw a crowd, A host, of golden daffodils;

英文诗歌赏析 To Dorothy

Perfect Relationship in an Imperfect Way Nobody is perfect. Every person has his unique feature. There is no need to change one’s characteristics to fit another person. People in love always want to change each other so that they can have a better and steadier relationship. But if you love a person, you should love his bright points and drawbacks together. In “To Dorothy”, Marvin Bell talks about this kind of love that you even love each other’s shortcomings. He discusses how he thinks of Dorothy. He discusses what Dorothy did in his life and what his reaction was. He also indicates what he would feel if Dorothy left him. In “To Dorothy”, Marvin Bell tells us we can have a perfect relationship in an imperfect way. This poem obviously talks about the relationship between the poet, Marvin Bell and Dorothy who may be Marvin Bell’s lover, wife, or relative and so on. In the first place, Marvin Bell tells us he thinks Dorothy is not beautiful. I think this may indicate that Dorothy is a not a perfect person in his eyes. “To Dorothy You are not beautiful exactly. You are beautiful, inexactly.” (Marvin Bell, 1) From here on, we can know that Marvin Bell knows clearly that Dorothy is not beautiful and perfect, because he uses two sentences which are the exactly same meaning to express the similar ideas. From anotherperspective, however, maybe there is another meaning that we can conclude from the two sentences. Using two similar sentences may express the poet’s hesitation. In the first sentence, Marvin Bell does think Dorothy is not exactly beautiful, but in the second sentence, in his eyes, Dorothy is

莎士比亚-sonnet-18-29-66的中文翻译及评析

18莎士比亚的十四行诗总体上表现了一个思想:爱征服一切。他的诗充分肯定了人的价值、赞颂了人的尊严、个人的理性作用。诗人将抽象的概念转化成具体的形象,用可感可见的物质世界,形象生动地阐释了人文主义的命题。 诗的开头将“你”和夏天相比较。自然界的夏天正处在绿的世界中,万物繁茂地生长着,繁阴遮地,是自然界的生命最昌盛的时刻。那醉人的绿与鲜艳的花一道,将夏天打扮得五彩缤纷、艳丽动人。但是,“你”却比夏天可爱多了,比夏天还要温婉。五月的狂风会作践那可爱的景色,夏天的期限太短,阳光酷热地照射在繁阴班驳的大地上,那熠熠生辉的美丽不免要在时间的流动中凋残。这自然界最美的季节和“你”相比也要逊色不少。 而“你”能克服这些自然界的不足。“你”在最灿烂的季节不会凋谢,甚至“你”美的任何东西都不会有所损失。“你”是人世的永恒,“你”会让死神的黑影在遥远的地方停留,任由死神的夸口也不会死去。“你”是什么?“你”与人类同在,你在时间的长河里不朽。那人类精神的精华——诗,是你的形体吗?或者,你就是诗的精神,就是人类的灵魂。 诗歌在形式上一改传统的意大利十四行诗四四三三体,而是采用了四四四二体:在前面充分地发挥表达的层次,在充分的铺垫之后,用两句诗结束全诗,点明主题。全诗用新颖巧妙的比喻,华美而恰当的修饰使人物形象鲜明、生气鲜活。诗人用形象的表达使严谨的逻辑推理变得生动有趣、曲折跌宕,最终巧妙地得出了人文主义的结论。 二十九首就是其中的一首。 这首诗热情地歌颂爱情,诗人在创作这首诗 时,充分发挥了十四行诗的长处,采用了“先抑后 扬”手法,层层推进,波澜起伏,道出了诗人的思想 感情发展变化过程,开头四句这样写道: When ,in disgrace with Fortune and men’ eyes , s I all alone beweep my outcast state , And trouble deaf heaven with my bootless cries , And look upon myself ,and curse my fate , 从这四句我们可以读出,一开始诗人悲悲切切地 唱出自己的悲惨处境“in disgrace with Fortune and , men’ eyes (失去了幸福,又遭人白眼。”,慨叹自 s )

十二篇经典英文诗歌赏析

十二篇经典英文诗歌赏析 大家都来看一下,学习一下吧。 【1】Rain雨 Rain is falling all around, 雨儿在到处降落, It falls on field and tree, 它落在田野和树梢, It rains on the umbrella here, 它落在这边的雨伞上,And on the ships at sea. 又落在航行海上的船只。 by R. L. Stevenson, 1850-1894 【2】What Does The Bee Do? What does the bee do? 蜜蜂做些什么? Bring home honey. 把蜂蜜带回家。 And what does Father do? 父亲做些什么? Bring home money. 把钱带回家。 And what does Mother do? 母亲做些什么? Lay out the money. 把钱用光。 And what does baby do?婴儿做些什么? Eat up the honey. 把蜜吃光。 by C. G. Rossetti, 1830-1894 【3】O Sailor, Come Ashore啊!水手,上岸吧 (Part I) O sailor, come ashore 啊!水手,上岸吧 What have you brought for me? 你给我带来什么? Red coral , white coral, 海里的珊瑚, Coral from the sea. 红的,白的。 (Part II) I did not dig it from the ground 它不是我从地下挖的,Nor pluck it from a tree; 也不是从树上摘的; Feeble insects made it 它是暴风雨的海裹 In the stormy sea. 弱小昆虫做成的。

相关文档
最新文档