古典自由主义与现代自由主义以及现代保守主义

古典自由主义与现代自由主义以及现代保守主义
古典自由主义与现代自由主义以及现代保守主义

Classical Liberalism

vs.

Modern Liberalism and Modern Conservatism In the history of politics, there is only one fundamental, abiding issue: It is individualism vs. collectivism. Do individuals have the right to pursue their own happiness, as Thomas Jefferson thought and as the Declaration of Independence deemed self-evident? Or do we have an obligation to live our lives for the community or the state, as most societies have claimed throughout most of history?

Yet if this is the paramount political issue, why is it not forthrightly debated in presidential elections and in other contests for public office? The reason is that American political debates tend to be dominated by modern liberalism and modern conservatism —approaches to politics that are properly called ―sociologies‖ rather than ―ideologies.‖ Modern liberalism is not completely collectivist; nor is it completely individualistic. It has elements of both doctrines. The same is true of conservatism. Neither view provides a coherent approach to politics, built up from first principles. Instead, they both reflect a process that is akin to picking items from a dinner menu. What is chosen is a matter of taste rather than a matter of thought. Just as people with similar tastes in food tend to frequent the same restaurants, people with the same tastes in politics tend to vote for the same candidates.

What that leaves us with are candidates, platforms and political parties whose ideas are inconsistent and often incoherent. The thoughtful voter may sometimes vote for the conservative, sometimes for the liberal and sometimes just abstain.

The classical liberal perspective will not solve this problem, but it will help us better understand it.

Classical Liberalism as an Ideology

Classical liberalism was the political philosophy of the Founding Fathers. It permeates the Constitution, the Federalist Papers and many other documents produced by the people who created the American system of government. Many emancipationists who opposed slavery were essentially classical liberals, as were the suffragettes, who fought for equal rights for women.1 Basically, classical liberalism is based on a belief in liberty. Even today, one of the clearest statements of this philosophy is found in the Declaration of Independence. In 1776, most people believed that rights came from government. People thought they had only such rights as government elected to give them. But following British philosopher John Locke, Jefferson argued that it‘s the other way arou nd. People have rights apart from government, as part of their nature. Further, people can both form governments and dissolve them. The only legitimate purpose of government is to protect these rights.

1 David Boaz, Libertarianism: A Primer (New York, N.Y.: Free Press, 1997), ch. 2.

The 19th century was the century of classical liberalism. Partly for that reason it was also the century of ever-increasing economic and political liberty, relative international peace, relative price stability and unprecedented economic growth. By contrast, the 20th century was the century that rejected classical liberalism. Partly for that reason, it was the century of dictatorship, depression and war. Nearly 265 million people were killed by their own governments (in addition to all the deaths from wars!) in the 20th century – more than in any previous century and possibly more than in all previous centuries combined.2

All forms of collectivism in the 20th century rejected the classical liberal notion of rights and all asserted in their own way that need is a claim. For the communists, the needs of the class (proletariat) were a claim against every individual. For the Nazis, the needs of the race were a claim. For fascists (Italian-style) and for architects of the welfare state, the needs of society as a whole were a claim. Since in all these systems the state is the personification of the class, the race, society as a whole, etc., all these ideologies imply that, to one degree or another, individuals have an obligation to live for the state.

Yet, the ideas of liberty survived. Indeed, almost everything that is good about modern liberalism (mainly its defense of civil liberties) comes from classical liberalism. And almost everything that is good about modern conservatism (mainly its defense of economic liberties) also comes from classical liberalism.

Modern Liberalism and Conservatism as Sociologies One of the difficulties in describing political ideas is that the people who hold them are invariably more varied and complex than the ideas themselves. Take Southern Democrats, for example. For most of the 20th century, right up through the 1960s and even into the 1970s, virtually every Democratic politician in the South was an advocate of segregation and Jim Crow laws. This group included Arkansas Sen. J. William Fulbright (a favorite of the liberal media because of his opposition to the Vietnam War); North Carolina‘s Sen. Sam Ervin (an ardent constitutionalist and another liberal favorite because his Senate hearings led to the downfall of Richard Nixon); Lyndon Johnson (who as president changed his public views on race and pushed through the Civil Rights Act of 1964); such economic populists as Louisiana Gov. Huey Long and Alabama Gov. George Wallace; West Virginia Sen. Robert Byrd, one-time Ku Klux Klan member and king of pork on Capitol Hill; and small government types, such as South Carolina‘s Sen. Strom Thurmond (who changed his views on race, began hiring black staffers and then switched parties and became a Republican).

This group held the balance of political power in Congress throughout most of the post-World War II period. T o even try to use words like ―conservative‖ and ―liberal‖ when describing them is more likely to mislead than to shed any useful light. With that caution, let us attempt a brief summary.

As reflected on the editorial pages of The New York Times, in the New Republic, and in Slate and other forums, contemporary liberals tend to believe in an almost unrestricted right to abortion and actively encourage stem cell research and sometimes even euthanasia. Yet they

2 Rudolph J. Rummel, Statistics of Democide: Genocide and Mass Murder since 1900 (Berlin-Hamburg-Munster: Lit Verlag, 1998).

think the state should never execute someone, not even a vicious serial killer. As reflected in National Review, the Weekly Standard and other forums, contemporary conservatives tend to hold the opposite views.

Liberals tend to believe that marijuana consumption should be legal, even for recreational use. Yet they are quite content to have the government deny terminal cancer patients access to experimental drugs. Conservatives tend to hold the opposite opinion.

In elections, most liberals support restricting the role of financial capital (money); but they want no restrictions on real capital (printing presses, radio and TV broadcast facilities) or organizational capital (labor union get-out-the-vote resources). Most conservatives are at least consistent in opposing almost any restriction other than mandatory disclosure.

By and large, conservatives believe in punishment, liberals in rehabilitation. Conservatives believe in tough love; liberals are more likely to coddle. Conservatives tend to favor school choice; liberals tend to oppose it. Many anti-war liberals support the military draft; many pro-war conservatives oppose conscription.

Is there some theory that connects these diverse views and gives them coherence? Perhaps. But it is doubtful that a garden-variety liberal or conservative could produce such a theory. Instead, how a person selects from the menu of policy options is more likely to be determined by where he went to school, where he lives and with whom he socializes. These choices reflect socialization, rather than abstract thought.3

There is, however, one difference between conservatives and liberals that is neither random nor chaotic. It is a difference that is systematic and predictable.

Whereas conservatism and liberalism are both outgrowths of classical liberal thought, they differ in what they accept and reject of their intellectual roots. Conservatism tends to accept the classical liberal commitment to economic liberty but rejects many of its applications to the noneconomic realm. Liberalism accepts the classical liberal commitment to civil liberties but largely rejects the idea of economic rights.4

As libertarians are wont to say, liberals want government in the boardroom but not in the bedroom. Conservatives want the reverse. Much more is involved, however, than bedrooms and boardrooms.

The Sociology of Modern Liberalism. Most liberals — at least mainstream liberals —believe you should be able to say anything you like (other than yelling fire in a crowded theater), no matter how much it offends and, for the most part, no matter how seditious. They also believe you should be able to publish almost anything as a matter of right. But they reject the idea of economic rights. They reject, for example, the notion of a right to freely sell one‘s services in the labor market. The New York Times in particular supports minimum wage legislation that keeps people from working if they cannot produce at least $7.25 an hour.

3 A number of studies have discovered that conservatives and liberals have different personality types. See, for example, Mathew Wolssner and April Kelly-Wolssner, ―Left Pipeline: Why Conservatives Don‘t Get Doctorates,‖ American Enterprise Institute, forthcoming.

4Barack Obama, for example, has been described as a ―civil liberalism‖ who nonetheless favors all manner of government intervention into the economy. See Jeffrey Rosen, ―A Card Carrying Civil Libertarian,‖ The New York Times, March 1, 2008.

Similarly, in the liberal view of the world, the butcher, the baker and the candlestick maker have no fundamental right to enter their chosen professions and sell their goods to the public. The medieval guilds that Adam Smith criticized were in this view not violating any fundamental rights when they restricted entry, controlled prices and output and imposed other monopolistic constraints. The same principle applies to modern special interest legislation.

Liberals are not advocates of special interest legislation per se. But they are apologists for it in the sense they believe that economic regulations should be decided by democratic political institutions, not by court-enforced rights to freedom of contract. So if butchers, bakers and candlestick makers succeed in obtaining special interest favors from government at the expense of everyone else, that is a legitimate exercise of political power.

The New York Times believes that you have a right to engage in almost any sexual activity in the privacy of your own bedroom. But the Times does not believe you have a fundamental right to rent your bedroom (or any other room) to your sexual partner – or to anyone else for that matter. Indeed, the Times is fully supportive of the principle of government regulation of who can rent to whom, for how long, under what circumstances, and at what price.

The liberal‘s view of rights is closely connected to the issue of trust. The editorial page of The New York Times does not trust government to read our mail or listen to our phone calls —even if the caller is talking to young Arab males behaving suspiciously. Yet the Times editorial writers are completely comfortable with having government control their retirement income, even though Social Security has been managed like a Ponzi scheme. They are also willing to cede control to government over their (and everyone else‘s) health care, including the power to make rationing decisions about who lives and who dies!

The Sociology of Modern Conservatism. Most conservatives — at least mainstream conservatives — believe in economic rights. Individuals should be able to freely sell their labor to any buyer or enter almost any profession and sell goods and services to the market as a matter of freedom of exchange. Any restrictions on these rights are justified only if there is some overriding general welfare concern.

Conservatives are far more willing than liberals to restrict freedom of thought and expression, however. For example, some believe that anyone should be able to make a flag (with wages and working conditions determined in a free labor market) and anyone should be able to sell a flag (fetching whatever price the market will bear), but they are quite willing to impose government controls on what can be done with the flag, including how it can be displayed, whether it can be worn, etc.

Is flag desecration obnoxious, reprehensible and unpatriotic? Of course. But the First Amendment was not written to protect the views of the majority. It was written to protect dissent.

Many conservatives, given a free hand, would impose additional government restrictions on our noneconomic liberties. In the past, conservatives were quite willing to control the books and magazines we read, the movies we watch, etc. These were the same people who believed that what went on in the workplace was none of the government‘s business.

At the time of its founding, America was one of the few countries in the world that did not have a state religion. This was no accident or oversight. The founders themselves were a religiously diverse group. Thomas Jefferson removed all mystical (spiritual) references from the

Bible and bequeathed us the Jefferson Bible. Tom Paine‘s Age of Reason was a wholesale attack on Christianity. And although the overwhelming majority at the time were Christian, America‘s second and third presidents (Jefferson and Adams) were Deists and some argue that Washington was as well.5

The founders clearly did not intend to remove religion from the public square. They did intend for the American system of government, at least at the federal level,to be pluralistic and tolerant with respect to religion. This is in contrast to some modern conservatives who would like to use the power of the state to impose their religious views on the culture.

Conservativism, Liberalism and the Courts. As noted in ―What Is Classical Liberalism?‖, the U.S. Supreme Court has increasingly sided with the liberal view of rights over the conservative view. Throughout the 20th century, Court rulings strengthened substantive First Amendment rights, as well as procedural rights related to most noneconomic liberties. At the same time, the Court weakened (indeed, eliminated) constitutional protections for substantive economic rights.

As a result, you have today an almost unrestrained constitutional right to say whatever you want to say. In any attempt by government to limit your speech, the Court will start with the presumption that you are exercising your First Amendment rights and the burden of proof will be on government to show why there is a compelling public interest in restraining you.

On the other hand, you have virtually no constitutionally protected rights to acquire and own property or engage in voluntary exchange. There is almost no constitutional constraint on government‘s power to prevent you from entering virtually any professi on or to regulate what you produce, how you produce it, or the terms under which you sell your output to others. In any conflict over government‘s economic regulatory power and your freedom of action, the Court will presume the government is acting within its authority and you will face a very strong burden to prove otherwise.

Platonic Roots of Conservative and Liberal Sociologies. The distinction between economic and civil liberties actually has its roots in philosophy. It rests on an idea that goes all the way back to Plato. Whether the distinction is between consciousness and reality, mind and body, mental and physical, spiritual and material, etc., all philosophers in the Platonic tradition have focused on two fundamentally different dimensions of human life. And following Plato, they have all believed that the world of thought is somehow more important, more moral, and more pure than the world of everyday affairs, and certainly more so than the world of commerce.

What follows from that distinction? Actually not very much. One could argue (as liberals do) that unimpeded thought and the benefits that flow from it are too important to be left to politicians to regulate the way they regulate commodities. Or one could argue (as conservatives do) that culture and mores and the ideas that nurture and support them are too important to be left to the vagaries of a laissez faire market for ideas.

The Impossibility of Consistent Conservative and Liberal Thought. Regardless of one‘s view of the mind-body dichotomy, the case for freedom of thought is not stronger than, weaker than, or any different from the case for freedom of contract. Just as there are externalities in the world of commerce, so there are externalities in the world of ideas. Just as

5 David L. Holms, The Faith of the Founding Fathers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).

public goods exist in the economy, so there are public-good type ideas in the culture. For every argument against a laissez faire economy, there is an equally persuasive argument against laissez faire cultures, laissez faire mores and a completely free market for ideas.

Or if the case for government intervention is stronger in one realm than in the other it is not clear where the stronger case lies. This helps us understand why consistent classical liberalism makes no distinction between freedom of thought and freedom of commerce. Both are subsumed under the general notion that people have a right to pursue their own happiness in any realm.

Any attempt to argue for differential rights fails on close examination. As noted, most liberals favor minimum wage laws that prevent common laborers from working if they cannot produce goods and services worth, say, $7.25 an hour. Yet these very same pundits would recoil in horror at the idea of a law which prevents people from being authors, playwrights and artists unless they can produce a minimum annual income. On what basis can one argue for economic freedom for musicians, painters and novelists while denying it to everyone else? There is no basis.

There is an even more fundamental problem with applying Platonic distinctions to politics. Although in theory we can separate mind and body, spiritual and material, etc., in practice these realms are not separable. Freedom of speech is a meaningless right without the economic right to acquire space, buy a megaphone and invite others to hear your message. Freedom of press is a meaningless right if one does not have the economic right to buy paper, ink and printing presses. Freedom of association is a meaningless right if one cannot own property or rent property or otherwise acquire the right to use the premises where a group can assemble.

The idea that political rights are meaningless without economic rights was made abundantly clear in recent presidential elections in Russia, where international chess star Garry Kasparo v sought to challenge President Vladimir Putin‘s hand-picked successor. Russian law requires that each candidate be endorsed at a meeting of at least 500 citizens. Yet under pressure from Putin, every landlord in Moscow refused to rent Kasparov‘s group a hall where they could hold a meeting. Unable to acquire the economic right to exercise his political right, Kasparov was forced to withdraw from the race.

Conservatism, Liberalism and the Reform of Institutions. Classical liberals were reformers. Throughout the 19th century, they reformed economic and civil institutions —abolishing slavery, extending the right to vote to blacks and eventually to women, expanding the protections of the Bill of Rights to state and local governments and creating a largely free market economy. Indeed, part of the notion of what it meant to be a ―liberal‖ was to favor reform.

In the 20th century, those with a zeal for reform continued calling themselves ―liberals,‖ even as they abandon the belief in economic freedom, while those who resisted reform took to mantel of ―conservatism.‖ In the words of National Review publisher, William F. Buckley, conservatives were ―standing athwart history and crying Stop!‖

This aspect of the two sociologies is most unfortunate. As the last century grew to a close it became obvious all over the world that economic collectivism did not work. Communism didn‘t work, socialism didn‘t work, Fascism didn‘t work and the welfare st ate didn‘t work. So in the economic realm the great need is to privatize, deregulate, and empower individual citizens.

The natural people to lead this reformation are conservatives, who profess belief in the goals. Yet conservatives have lacked in the needed skills, having spent the better part of a century on defense. This may explain why so often needed reforms have been implemented in other countries by parties of the left. Even in the United States, the effort to deregulate our most oppressive regulatory agencies began under President Jimmy Carter and had the support of such liberal stalwarts as Sen. Edward Kennedy.

Other Varieties of Liberalism and Conservatism

Not all liberals think alike. Nor do all conservatives. Two strands of these sociologies deserve special attention, particularly in light of the contrast with classical liberalism.

Liberal Aberration: Political Correctness and the Emergence of Group Rights. A variation of modern liberalism is popular among faculties at college campuses. Its adherents reject not only the idea of individual economic rights, but also the idea of individual rights as such. Instead, they believe that people enjoy rights and incur obligations as members of groups.

On this view, a black American should enjoy rights that are denied to white Americans — not because of some injury or harm one has done to the other or because of some contract, but merely because one is black and one is white. Similarly, Native American Indians should have rights that a black does not have. A woman should have rights that a man does not have.

Adherents of this view believe there is no such thing as an individual right to freedom of speech or expression or association. What rights or privileges you have depend on what group you are a member of, and the state may properly enforce such distinctions. For example, speech that is permissible if the speaker is black might be actionable if the speaker were white, Asian or Hispanic, depending on how the speech affects the sensibilities of other blacks. Or if blacks or Hispanics, say, form groups and exclude others, that is generally permissible; but the same actions by a group of whites or any of the European ethnic groups would probably be proscribed.

Assigning rights and responsibilities to groups rather than individuals is at the heart of collectivism. Political correctness is a sort of barnyard version of collectivism. In this sense, the type of liberalism that is popular on college campuses is far more consistent than mainstream liberalism. This version of liberalism rejects individualism as such.

Such consistency, however, exists only in the abstract. In practice, politically correct liberalism is anything but consistent. For example, the standard justification for giving group A more rights than group B is some injustice committed by B‘s ancestors against A‘s ancestors. Yet among the black students at Harvard University (all of whom presumably qualify for racial preferences), only one-third are unambiguous descendants of slaves. More than half are immigrants! Harvard and many other prestigious universities are assigning privileges to students not based on past grievances but on skin color alone.6

Conservative Aberration: Protectionism and the Rise of Tribal Politics. There is a strand of conservatism that rejects the thinking of mainstream economists for the last 200 years. As represented most visibly by columnist and sometime presidential candidate Pat Buchanan,

6 Sara Rimer and Karen W. Arenson, ―Top Colleges Take More Blacks, but Which Ones?‖ New York Times, June 24, 2004.

this group of thinkers wants government to impose tariffs and quotas and other restrictions to prevent foreigners from competing with domestic companies and their workers.7

Yet as Adam Smith explained more than two centuries ago, trade does not reduce the number of jobs. Instead it changes the nature of work people do. Furthermore, trade is income enhancing. It makes citizens better off, on the average, than they otherwise would have been –although some individual incomes may fall as others rise in the process. So what Buchanan‘s agenda is really about is not saving jobs or protecting incomes. It‘s about saving some jobs at the expense of other jobs and preventing s ome people‘s income losses at the expense of other people‘s income gains.

Conservatives who hold these beliefs view the world from the right in exactly the same way as some trade unionists view the world from the left. They believe that people are entitled to their jobs for no other reason than that‘s what they happen to be doing. They are entitled to their current incomes for no other reason than that‘s what they happen to be earning.

Readers of ―What Is Classical Liberalism?‖ will have no difficulty seeing that Buchanan‘s views are a small scale version of the economic views of Franklin Roosevelt. Whereas Buchanan focuses on trade, Roosevelt understood that jobs and incomes are threatened by exchange as such. Whereas Buchanan wants to freeze in place the international economy, Roosevelt wanted to freeze in place the domestic economy. The motives are the same. The vision is the same. And although these views today sometimes parade und er the ―progressive‖label (at least when the advocate is on the political left), they are anything but progressive. The desire to freeze economic relationships and prevent the kind of creative destruction that is essential in all growing economies is the epitome of ―reactionary‖ thought.

Buchanan is not only an economic protectionist, he is also a cultural protectionist who wants to stop the flow of immigration. There are legitimate (classical liberal) reasons to be concerned about illegal immigration — not the least of which is the practice of subsidizing it with free education, free medical care and other public services. Buchanan‘s main objection is different. He wants government to protect the culture from immigrants. Also, Buchanan would go much further than most other conservatives in restricting freedom of expression. Although they are viewed as poles apart, Buchanan actually has a lot in common with the politically correct crowd on college campuses. He believes, for example, that Christians, Muslims and Jews should not have to tolerate irreverent insults to their beliefs and has even hinted that it may be permissible to outlaw blasphemy.

Historical Roots of Conservatism and Liberalism

Where do conservatism and liberalism come from? Strangely, this is a question that is rarely asked. It is even more rarely answered.

In American politics these days, it is increasingly common for those on the left to call themselves ―progressives‖ rather than ―liberals.‖ The term is apt in the sense that much of modern liberalism has its roots in the Progressive Era, which flourished in the first several decades of the 20th century. Interestingly, much of contemporary conservatism also finds its roots in that era. In fact it‘s probably fair to say that while the best of modern liberal and

7 Patrick J. Buchanan, Day of Reckoning: How Hubris, Ideology, and Greed Are Tearing America Apart (New York, N.Y.: Thomas Dunne Books, 2007).

conservative ideas are extensions of classical liberalism, their worst ideas are products of progressivism.8

To many people, the term ―Progressive Era‖ evokes fond caricatures of Teddy Roosevelt and such reforms as safe food, the elimination of child labor and the eight-hour work day. Yet real progressivesm was much more profound and far more sinister. Here is how Jonah Goldberg describes the World War I presidency of Woodrow Wilson:9

The first ap pearance of modern totalitarianism in the Western world wasn‘t in

Italy or Germany but in the United States of America. How else would you

describe a country where the world‘s first modern propaganda ministry was

established; political prisoners by the thousands were harassed, beaten, spied

upon, and thrown in jail simply for expressing private opinions; the national

leader accused foreigners and immigrants of injecting treasonous ―poison‖ into

the American bloodstream; newspapers and magazines were shut down for

criticizing the government; nearly a hundred thousand government propaganda

agents were sent out among the people to whip up support for the regime and its

war; college professors imposed loyalty oaths on their colleagues; nearly a

quarter-million goons were given legal authority to intimidate and beat ―slackers‖

and dissenters; and leading artists and writers dedicated their crafts to

proselytizing for the government?

Some readers may be inclined to dismiss these tyrannies as unfortunate excesses of wartime, much as Abraham Lincoln suspended habeas corpus and trampled on other constitutional liberties during the Civil War. The difference is that Lincoln truly believed in Jeffersonian democracy and classical liberal principles. Wilson, by contrast, was our first Ph.D. in the White House, and in his books and other writings he made clear his complete rejection of the ideas of Jefferson and classical liberalism; as Ronald Pestritto notes, liberty in his view, was ―not found in freedom from state actions but instead in one‘s obedience to the laws of the state.‖10

Wilson was by no means alone. He was at the epicenter of an intellectual trend that swept the Western world in the early part of the last century. In Russia there was Bolshevism. In Italy, Fascism. In America, Britain and other parts of Europe, the new ideas were called progressivism. There were, of course, many differences — political, moral and otherwise — in the content of these isms and huge differences in resulting policies. But all had one thing in common: they saw classical liberalism as the intellectual enemy and they disliked liberalism far more than they disliked the ideas of each other.

At the time of the Wilson presidency, progressives did not view the exercise of state power and the violation of individual rights as a war-time exception to be set aside in times of peace. To the contrary, Herbert Croly (founding editor of the New Republic), John Dewey

8See Ronald J. Pestritto, ―Liberals, Conservatives and Limited Government: Are We All Progressives Now?‖ Unpublished manuscript, January 28, 2008.

9 Jonah Goldberg, Liberal Fascism: The Secret History of the American Left from Mussolini to the Politics of Meaning (New York, N.Y.: Doubleday, 2007), pp. 11-12.

10 Ronald J. Pestritto, Woodrow Wilson and the Roots of Modern Liberalism (Lanham, Md.: Roman & Littlefield, 2005), p. 55.

(father of progressive education), Walter Lippman (perhaps the century‘s most influential political writer), Richard Ely (founder of the American Economic Association) and many others saw war as an opportunity to rid the country of classical liberalism and the doctrine of laissez faire.

In fact, the primary domestic objective of progressives was to create in peacetime what Wilson had accomplished during war. They were able to do so a little more than a decade later. Franklin Roosevelt was Assistant Secretary of the Navy under Wilson, and when he led Democrats back to the White House in 1932 he brought with him an army of intellectuals and bureaucrats who shared the progressive-era vision. Indeed, most of the ―alphabet soup‖ of agencies set up during the Great Depression were continuations of various boards and committees set up during World War I.

Perhaps because of World War II, the revelations of all the gory details of the Nazi Holocaust, and the subsequent Cold War, it quickly became inconvenient, if not acutely embarrassing, for historians and other commentators to remind people of the state of intellectual relations before hostilities broke out. At that time, it was commonplace for intellectuals on the left to be enamored of Lenin‘s communist regime in Russia. And almost everyone who was enamored of Lenin was also an admirer of Mussolini‘s Fascist government in Italy. For example, General Hugh ―Iron Pants‖ Johnson, who ran Roosevelt‘s National Recovery Administration (NRA) kept a picture of Mussolini hanging on his wall. The admiration was often mutual. Some writers for publications in Nazi Germany and Fascist Italy wrote of their fascination with Roosevelt‘s New Deal.

What was the political philosophy that all these very diverse people shared? Basically, the idea that nations are ―organic entities in need of direction by an avant-garde of scientific experts and social planners,‖ who would ―erode the ?artificial,‘ legal or cultural boundaries between family and state, public and private, business and the ?public good.‘‖11 As Goldberg explains:12

The reason so many progressives were intrigued by both Mussolini‘s and Lenin‘s

―experiments‖ is simple: they saw their reflection in the European looking glass.

Philosophically, organizationally, and politically the progressives were as close to

authentic, homegrown fascists as any movement America has ever produced.

Militaristic, fanatically nationalist, imperialist, racist, deeply involved in the

promotion of Darwinian eugenics, enamored of the Bismarckian welfare state,

statist beyond modern reckoning, the progressives represented the American

flowering of a transatlantic movement, a profound reorientation toward the

Hegelian and Darwinian collectivism imported from Europe at the end of the

nineteenth century.

What was the progressives‘approach to economic policy? Given Teddy Roosevelt‘s attacks on ―the trusts‖ and the muckraking novels of Upton Sinclair and Ida Tarbel l, one might be inclined to think that progressives were anti-business. Yet nothing could be further from the truth.

11 Goldberg, Liberal Fascism, pp. 247 and 297.

12 Ibid., p. 12.

As the leftist historian Gabriel Kolko has documented, the Interstate Commerce Commission (ICC) — our first federal regulatory agency — was dominated by, and served the interest of, the railroads. Similarly, the regulatory apparatus created by the Meat Inspection Act of 1906 served the interests of large meat packers. Safety standards were invariably already being met — or were easily accommodated — by large companies. But the regulations forced many small enterprises out of business and made it difficult for new ones to enter the industry. This same pattern — of regulatory agencies serving the interests of the regulated — was repeated with the establishment of almost all subsequent regulatory agencies as well. For this reason, Kolko called the entire Progressive Era the ―triumph of conservatism.‖13

The practices Kolko described were elevated to a refined science by Wilson‘s War Industries Board (WIB) during World War I. Trade associations were allowed to organize along industry lines — controlling output, setting prices and effectively functioning as an industry-by-industry system of cartels. By the time Franklin Roosevelt established the NRA during the Depression years, planners could draw not only upon the experience of the Wilson-era WIB, but also on the far more extensive experience of Mussolini‘s Italian economy — which was organized in the same way.

There are even more eerie transatlantic parallels. The symbol of the NRA was the Blue Eagle, which businesses were expected to hang on their doors to show compliance with NRA rules. Newspapers in both America and Germany compared the Blue Eagle to the swastika and the German Reich eagle. A quasi-official army of informants and even goon squads helped monitor compliance. Nuremberg-style Blue Eagle rallies were held, including a gathering of 10,000 strong at Madison Square Garden. A New York City Blue Eagle parade was larger than the ticker-tape parade celebrating Charles Lindbergh‘s crossing of the Atlantic.14

Through the NRA, the federal government — backed by the full force of criminal law —intruded into virtually every transaction. An immigrant dry cleaner spent three months in jail for charging 35 cents to press a suit when the code required a minimum charge of 40 cents. Another case —one that went all the way to the Supreme Court — involved immigrant brothers who ran a small poultry business. Among the laws they were accused of violating was a requirement that buyers of chickens not select the chicken they were buying. Instead the buyer needed to reach into the coop and take the first chicken that came to hand. (The reason: buyers would be tempted to take the best chicken, leaving less desirable options for other buyers.)15

In Schechter Poultry Corp. v. United States (the so-called ―sick chicken‖ case), a unanimous Supreme Court declared the NRA unconstitutional. Roosevelt responded by trying to intimidate the justices and by asking Congress to expand the number of justices so that he could pack the court with judges more to his liking. Although he lost the battle, Roosevelt eventually won the war. Today it is highly unlikely that an NRA would be declared unconstitutional.

The interests of progressive era intellectuals was not limited to economics. They saw the state as properly involved in almost every aspect of social life. Herbert Croly envisioned a state 13 Gabriel Kolko, The Triumph of Conservatism: A Reinterpretation of American History, 1900-1916 (New York, N.Y.: Free Press, 1963).

14 Goldberg, Liberal Fascism, pp. 153-155.

15 Amity Shlaes, The Forgotten Man: A New History of the Great Depression (New York, N.Y.: Harper Collins, 2007), ch. 8.

that would even regulate who could marry and procreate. In this respect, he reflected the almost universal belief of progressives in eugenics. These days, there is a tendency to think that interest in racial purity began and ended in Hitler‘s Germany. In fact, virtually all intellectuals on the left in the early 20th century believed in state involvement in promoting a better gene pool. These included H.G. Wells, George Bernard Shaw, Sidney and Beatrice Webb (founders of Fabian Socialism), Harold Laski (the most respected British political scientist of the 20th century) and John Maynard Keynes (the most famous economist of the 20th century). Pro-eugenics articles routinely appeared in the leftwing New Statesman, the Manchester Guardian and in the United States in the New Republic.16

One of the ugliest stains on American public policy during the 20th century was the internment of 100,000 Japanese Americans during World War II by the Roosevelt Administration. Another stain is the resegregation of the White House under Wilson. One writer argues that these acts were consistent with the personal racial views of the presidents and that the Democratic party has a long history of racial bias it would like to forget.17 But similar views appeared in early editions of the conservative, pro-Republican National Review as well.18 The worst excesses on the right in the 20th century are usually associated with Senator Joe McCarthy; the hearings of the House Un-American Activities Committee (HUAC), including pressuring Hollywood actors to reveal their political activities and name the identities of their colleagues; and domestic surveillance of political enemies.

Yet all of these activities have roots in the Progressive Era as well. Joe McCarthy started his political life as a Democrat (and later switched to be a Republican) in Wisconsin — the most pro-progressive state in the union. As Goldberg observes, ―Red baiting, witch hunts, censorship and the like were a tradition in good standing among Wisconsin progressives and populists.‖ The HUAC was founded by another progressive Democrat, Samuel Dickstein, to investigate German sympathizers. D uring the ―Brown scare‖ of the 1940s, radio journalist Walter Winchell read the names of isolationists on the radio, calling them ―Americans we can do without.‖ Even American communists in this period supplied the names of ―German sympathizers.‖19 Civilian surveillance under American presidents in the modern era (for example under Republicans Richard Nixon and George W. Bush and under Democrats John Kennedy and Lyndon Johnson) are extensions of what went on earlier in the century. However, modern surveillance does not begin to compare in magnitude to what went on during the Wilson and Roosevelt presidencies.

The Need for a Neoclassical Synthesis

The use of the word ―progressive‖ by modern liberals is appropriate — to the degree that it reminds us of the historical and intellectual roots of much of liberal thinking. But there is another sense in which the word is very misleading. In general, there is nothing truly progressive

16 Goldberg, Liberal Fascism, ch. 7.

17 Bruce Bartlett, Wrong on Race: The Democratic Party’s Buried Past (New York, N.Y.: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008).

18 Paul Krugman, The Conscience of a Liberal (New York, N.Y.: W.W. Norton, 2007), pp. 101-104.

19 Ibid., pp. 224-225.

about modern progressives. That is, nothing in their thinking is forward looking. Invariably, the social model they have in mind is in the distant past. Many explicitly admit they would like to resurrect Roosevelt‘s New Deal.20

In this sense, most people on the left who use the word ―progressive‖ ar e actually reactionaries. And the problem is not only on the left. In general, the greatest intellectual danger we face is from reactionaries on the left and right.

Reactionaries (mainly on the left, but sometimes also on the right) want to freeze the economy — preserving the current allocation of jobs and the incomes that derive from those jobs. Although their current focus is on opposition to globalization and international trade, consistency requires them to oppose virtually all of the ―creative destruction‖ that Joseph Shumpeter said was inevitable in any dynamic, capitalistic economy.

Reactionaries (mainly on the right, but sometimes also on the left) want to freeze the culture. They see new ideas, different religions and different cultures as threats to their world view. Rather than allow ideas, religions and mores to compete in a pluralistic, tolerant society, they want to use the power of government to force their ideas on others.

Against these threats to liberty, the basic classical liberal understanding of rights is a powerful defense. I may disagree with the wage you work for, the conditions you work under, the hours you work and even the profession you have chosen. But in a free labor market, you do not have to ask my permission (or the permission of anyone else) in order to exercise your right to work. The same principle applies to the world of ideas. In a free society, you should not have to ask my permission (or anyone else‘s permission) to write a book, read a book, give a speech, hear a speech, read a magazine, watch a movie or listen to rock music.

The intellectual framework developed in the 18th and 19th centuries, however, is not sufficient.21 Two hundred years ago there were no weapons of mass destruction — no nuclear arms, no biological or chemical weapons. There was also no threat of global warming, and mankind‘s ability to harm the environment was much more limited than today.22 Also, there are today new frontiers. How do we determine who gets what satellite space in upper earth orbit, or who has rights to minerals on the floor of the sea? The ideas of John Locke may illuminate our search for answers, but they do not offer simple solutions.

To meet these newer challenges, what is needed is a neoclassical synthesis — a political theory that incorporates the best of modern conservatism and modern liberalism and discards the worst. I call such a theory neoclassical liberalism because it builds on the foundation laid by the founding fathers and brings the spirit of their concept of liberty into the 21st century.

We shall develop these ideas in future essays.

20 See, for example, Krugman, Conscience of a Liberal.

21John C. Goodman, ―Do Inalienable Rights Allow Punishment,‖ Liberty, Vol. 10, Issue 5, May 1997; and John C. Goodman, ―N-Space: the Final Frontier,‖ Liberty, Vol. 13, Issue 7, July 1999.

22 For an example of how a na?ve application of the 18th century view of rights applied to modern problems can lead to silliness, see Mur ray Rothbard‘s views on pollution; Murray Rothbard, ―Law, Property Rights and Air Pollution,‖ The CATO Journal, Vol. 2, No. 1, spring 1982.

20世纪70年代以后的保守自由主义

20世纪70年代以后的保守自由主义 保守自由主义(Conservative liberalism)是自由主义的变体之一,结合自由价值、政策与保守主义立场,或更简单地说,代表自由运动中的右派。 保守自由主义政党结合了自由主义政策与在社会、道德议题上较为传统的立场。[2] 他们普遍是经济自由主义的支持者,且常定义自身为法治政党。 两次世界大战以前,从德国到意大利,多数欧洲国家的政治阶级由保守自由主义者所主导。像是第一次世界大战等1917年以后发生的事件将较激进的古典自由主义带到较保守(温和)的自由主义。 在欧洲,不要将保守自由主义与自由保守主义混淆,自由保守主义是结合了保守主义观点与经济、社会和种族议题上的自由主义政策。 一、基本主张 主张维护17世纪以来的古典自由主义传统,反对以福利国家为目标、以加强政府干预为手段的现代自由主义改革。 分为两类:一类是以保守自由市场为重点的经济学家,如:哈耶克、布坎南、弗里德曼等;一类是以保守一般意义的个人自由和个人权利为特色的哲学家、政治学家,如:伯林、诺齐克、萨托利等。 在经济上,强调私有制和市场经济的有效性,批评国家干预所造成的经济恶果,认为政府职能的增加是对个人自由的威胁;在政治上,批评政府的低效率和官僚主义,以及对自由、民主、法治的破坏;在积极自由和消极自由的问题上,强调消极自由,认为积极自由会导致强制,破坏自由,而消极自由才是真正的自由;在自由和平等的问题上,强调自由的优先性;在民主问题上,反对“平等的民主”,主张回到”自由的民主”中去,强调间接民主,把政治交给那些选举出来的精英人物,主张“精英政治”。 二、代表人物及其思想 1、 2.

浅析中国现当代自由主义文学思潮

浅析中国现当代自由主义文学思潮 论文关键词:自由主义;本体观;特性;二律背反 论文摘要:自由主义思潮是一种思潮,在中国现代文坛表反映为要求“文学自由”的理论呼声与创作趋向。这股文学思潮发端于晚清,从五四刘建国前兴衰起伏三十年,建国后丧失生存空间,其特殊境遇中有着复杂的内蕴。文学上的自由主义思潮塑造了作家的独立人格,强化了作品人文精神和审美品格。然而它却面临着“功利主义和审美价值二律背反”的必然困境。 自由主义思想的萌芽,最早可追溯到古希腊时期,而现代意义上的自由主义则是17世纪以后才出现的。人们通常以洛克作为第一个真正具备自由主义特征的思想家。上这种极具平民性及广泛性的思想,在欧洲17世纪的科学革命和18世纪启蒙运动的催化下,从英国开始并迅速在欧美各地较发达的国家生根发芽,到”世纪达到全盛,直至20世纪才处于衰落状态(20世纪以后又获得新的发展)。自由主义所倡导的政治、公民(个人)权利以及对、自由企业和产权保护的提倡,对个人和自立观念的坚持等思想,在政治、经济和文化方面,深刻影响了近代世界的历史进程。“自由”已构成了现代性的根本价值。 中国的自由主义思潮和运动可谓生不逢时,当它开始萌芽之际,正值欧美的资产阶级自由主义思想处于衰落之时(正值社会逐渐沦入半殖民地半封建的深渊之时)。与自由主义在欧美民众中的普遍接受不同,中国的自由主义思想主要存在于思想文艺界的知识分子中间。它代表性的人物主要是一部分从欧美留学归来、深受西方自由主义思想影响的知识分子,如晚清时代的严复、康有为、梁启超、谭嗣同,以及民国时期的胡适、周作人、朱光潜、林语堂、粱实秋、沈从文、徐志摩等人。以他们为核心,形成了中国近现代独具特色的时断时续的自由主义政治文化思潮。笔者这里所要论及的中的自由主义思潮是指在近现代文学史上存在的,以那些深受西方自由主义思想影响的作家为主体,以维护文学的独立品格和作家创作心

自由主义的发展历程

关于自由主义的阐述 自由主义是一种意识形态、哲学,以自由作为主要政治价值的一系列思想流派的集合。 一、自由主义的发展历程 (一)革命时期的自由主义 1、背景: 革命时期的自由主义者面临的主要任务是反对封建专制,争取个人的政治权利,争取民主权利和宪政政府,所以,自由主义最早具备的内涵是政治自由主义。 2、发展过程: 17世纪,洛克(英国自由主义思想家)在其著作《政府论》《论宗教宽容》中,第一次系统地阐述了自由主义的政治主张:保障个人自由,生命权、自由权、财产权是公民天赋的,在法律允许的范围内,人民尽可以自由行动。国家的建立基于社会契约,国家权力必须受到限制。18世纪,欧洲自由主义的大本营从英国转移到法国。如孟德斯鸠、贡斯当和托克维尔,他们进一步发展了洛克的自由主义思想。 3、内涵: 第一,人生而平等,享有不可剥夺的自然权利 第二,有限政府论。政府只是保护个人自由权利和利益的工具。 第三,实行分权制度。国家权力分为立法、行政、对外权,有不同的机构行使。 4、理论影响

资产阶级革命时期的自由主义是具有进步意义的: 主张人生而平等、自由,反对封建等级制度和人身依附关系; 主张人具有生命、财产、自由权,反对封建神权和王权的残暴统治;主张社会契约论,反对君权神授,唤起了民众的自我意识; (二)自由资本主义时期的自由主义 1、背景: 资产阶级革命胜利后,随着自由主义思想在政治生活中的不断巩固,它的原则也日益扩大到经济领域,关注政府应以何种方式介入经济,经济自由主义的理论开始形成。 2、主要代表人物及理论内涵 亚当·斯密(经济自由主义理论的奠基者)经济自由主义,即国家对私人经济活动不加干预,采取自由放任的态度。政府的职能仅在于提供必要的保障,使个人追求利益的行为有可靠的外部环境。 杰瑞米·边沁、大卫·李嘉图、詹姆斯·密尔等同样倡导经济自由、契约自由和竞争自由,提出国家应奉行放任主义,赋予个人更大的自由活动余地。经济自由主义的核心内涵是对经济与财产权利的强调。它的基石是私有财产、市场经济和国家较少的干预。 3、影响 经济自由主义理论适应了当时资本主义自由竞争的需要。英国资产阶级革命后,生产力得到飞速发展,经过工业革命,生产技术优于世界上的任何国家。这时的工业资产阶级,在经济上不需要政府的帮助和支持,工业生产的社会化程度还不高,垄断还没有形成,因此,

英国新自由主义与费边社会主义的比较研究

英国新自由主义与费边社会主义的比较研究这项研究源于本文作者对19世纪80年代至一战前英国最重要的两个福利意识形态——即新自由主义和费边社会主义——的兴趣。二者是对高度工业化的社会所产生的种种政治、社会和伦理危机的积极回应,是那个时代的英国进步主义运动中最杰出的两个政治意识形态。在19世纪末英国所有政治意识形态当中,它们是最积极处理像赤贫、失业、疾病和教育等社会问题的两个意识形态,是支持英国社会改革 和福利国家的最重要力量。20世纪70年代以来,英语学术界的一个 公认的、但较为初步的论断是,19世纪与20世纪之交的英国新自由 主义与费边社会主义共享了大量政治概念(或者说政治价值),并且, 二者针对英国当时紧迫的社会问题提出的政策建议亦有颇多相似之处,以至于一同被置于"英国左派"的标签之下。然而,二者之间的重叠与差异尚未得到全面而系统的分析,二者之间的共识与分歧的性质也 尚未得到恰当的理解。在过去的福利意识形态研究中,无论是单维还 是二维的分析和比较,都过度简化了意识形态本身的复杂性,因此并 没有提供令人满意的阐释模式。本文尝试借鉴自20世纪90年代以来在政治意识形态研究方面的新进展,来对上述论断进行重新检视。从 功能的角度来看,政治意识形态被视作一套观念、信念、看法和价值,它们在公共政策方案的提供与控制等方面展开竞争,其目的是证成、 抗议或改变一个政治共同体的社会政治安排和进程。从形态学的角度来看,意识形态是政治概念以一种可持续的模式构成的复杂排列组合,这种排列组合的特征是通过核心概念、邻近概念和外缘概念构成独特

的意识形态场域。意识形态的内容广泛的内部结构安排为相互定义的政治概念确定了含义,消除了含义中的争议性。借助这种政治意识形态路径,本文可以把新自由主义与费边社会主义的功能视作为世纪之交英国的社会和政治转型、并为福利国家的建设提供理论基础和政策建议。本文试图通过对作为新自由主义代表的霍布豪斯与霍布森、以及作为费边社会主义代表的萧伯纳与韦伯夫妇进行细致的分本分析,并结合其他较为次要的思想家,来辨识这两个意识形态所涵盖的政治概念在各自的意识形态场域中所占据不同的位置、形成的不同排列组合和布局、以及由此生成的不同含义,来界定这两个政治意识形态之间的交叠并阐明二者之间的分疏。本文作者主张,在意识形态布局的核心区域中,新自由主义吸纳了共同体和福祉这两个要素,因此与费边社会主义产生了局部的交叠;在邻近区域中,民主和国家是这两个意识形态共同拥有的概念。然而,新自由主义者把"个性的自由发展"视作核心信念,但费边社会主义者往往把个性概念边缘化了;平等是新自由主义的另一个重要邻近概念,但在费边社会主义意识形态当中却处于核心地位,而且这两个意识形态还通过相当不同的邻近概念来确定平等的不同意义场域。在外缘区域中,这两个意识形态都支持福利国家政策,其中包括最低生活工资、养老金、工作权、社会保险等;但二者在福利措施的设计和制定上存在大量分歧,而这些分歧是核心和邻近区域的分歧在外缘区域的结果。因此,无论是在意识形态布局的核心结构、邻近概念还是周边地带,二者都既存在局部重叠又保留一定范围的差异。本文的上述论断对于政治思想研究和政治思考产生

自由主义的发展历程

自由主义的发展历程公司内部编号:(GOOD-TMMT-MMUT-UUPTY-UUYY-DTTI-

关于自由主义的阐述 自由主义是一种、哲学,以自由作为主要的一系列思想的集合。 一、自由主义的发展历程 (一)革命时期的自由主义 1、背景: 革命时期的自由主义者面临的主要任务是反对封建专制,争取个人的政治权利,争取民主权利和宪政政府,所以,自由主义最早具备的内涵是政治自由主义。 2、发展过程: 17世纪,洛克(英国自由主义思想家)在其着作《政府论》《论宗教宽容》中,第一次系统地阐述了自由主义的政治主张:保障个人自由,生命权、自由权、财产权是公民天赋的,在法律允许的范围内,人民尽可以自由行动。国家的建立基于社会契约,国家权力必须受到限制。18世纪,欧洲自由主义的大本营从英国转移到法国。如孟德斯鸠、贡斯当和托克维尔,他们进一步发展了洛克的自由主义思想。 3、内涵: 第一,人生而平等,享有不可剥夺的自然权利 第二,有限政府论。政府只是保护个人自由权利和利益的工具。 第三,实行分权制度。国家权力分为立法、行政、对外权,有不同的机构行使。 4、理论影响 资产阶级革命时期的自由主义是具有进步意义的:

主张人生而平等、自由,反对封建等级制度和人身依附关系; 主张人具有生命、财产、自由权,反对封建神权和王权的残暴统治; 主张社会契约论,反对君权神授,唤起了民众的自我意识; (二)自由资本主义时期的自由主义 1、背景: 资产阶级革命胜利后,随着自由主义思想在政治生活中的不断巩固,它的原则也日益扩大到经济领域,关注政府应以何种方式介入经济,经济自由主义的理论开始形成。 2、主要代表人物及理论内涵 亚当·斯密(经济自由主义理论的奠基者)经济自由主义,即国家对私人经济活动不加干预,采取自由放任的态度。政府的职能仅在于提供必要的保障,使个人追求利益的行为有可靠的外部环境。 杰瑞米·边沁、大卫·李嘉图、詹姆斯·密尔等同样倡导经济自由、契约自由和竞争自由,提出国家应奉行放任主义,赋予个人更大的自由活动余地。经济自由主义的核心内涵是对经济与财产权利的强调。它的基石是私有财产、市场经济和国家较少的干预。 3、影响 经济自由主义理论适应了当时资本主义自由竞争的需要。英国资产阶级革命后,生产力得到飞速发展,经过工业革命,生产技术优于世界上的任何国家。这时的工业资产阶级,在经济上不需要政府的帮助和支持,工业生产的社会化程度还不高,垄断还没有形成,因此,自由主义的自由竞争、自由贸易的政策非常适合新兴资产阶级的需要。

当代西方政治思潮——保守主义

当代西方政治思潮——保守主义 本堂课所讲的主题是当代西方政治思潮之保守主义,主要内容概括为以下四个方面:一、保守主义的特征;二、保守主义的内涵;三、保守主义的类型;四、当代保守主义。 近代以来的主要意识形态或政治思潮为自由主义、保守主义、社会主义、法西斯主义、无政府主义、女性主义、环境主义、宗教基本教义派。 保守主义作为一种意识形态出现在法国大革命时期。文艺复兴以来的乐观主义认为:第一,世界的存在是有序的;第二,人类痛苦的来源并不是人的原罪,而是罪恶的社会。只要改造社会,痛苦就会最终从人类消失。保守主义的内涵指出,人类理解以及改变世界能力有限;罪恶,痛苦不仅仅是人类生活中暂时的因素,不仅仅产生于不公正的社会组织,而是人类生存中永恒的,不可消除的现象。保守主义两个基本涵义是:不完美主义和政治的有限性。保守主义认为人类社会的不完美是内在的,永久的,而不是暂时的。在这点上,保守主义不同于激进主义,也不同于反动派。保守主义,不是改变现状,也不是怀恋过去,而是保持现状。历史上的保守主义有:法国式,以梅斯特尔为代表的极端保守主义以及带有自由主义色彩的温和保守主义;德国式,发端可以追溯到早期政治浪漫主义,主要代表人物是诺瓦利斯;英国式,代表人物是柏可,其理论展示了保守主义的一些一般特性,如尊重传统,强调社会是有机体,是自然的产物,而不是人为设计的产物。保守主义的类型有,政治保守主义、文化保守主义、社会保守主义。政治保守主义,反对激烈变革,反对革命,维持现状。文化保守主义,强调传统文化的价值,反对自由主义的普遍主义理念,拒绝所有文化都会朝着现代化方向发展的预测,拒绝承认某种文化代表了人类社会的前进方向。社会保守主义,在德国浪漫主义时期表现得最为典型。保守主义者厌恶现代化带来的社会后果,如人与人关系的淡漠,城市化,环境污染等,他们憧憬田园诗般的生活,憧憬传统社会人与人之间的和谐,人与自然关系的和谐。没有一个自由主义者具备自由主义者的所有特征,其他主义者亦同。从1950年开始,出现了一场持续的保守主义革命,特别是美国。构成这种保守主义革命有多重势力:经济上的新自由主义;形形色色的文化保守主义;基督教右派;新保守主义。这些即为当代保守主义。在非西方国家中,则是世界范围的宗教与传统文化的复兴以及对启蒙运动的反动。当然在这些西方政治中的各种思潮,无所谓好亦无所谓坏,都有其存在的意义。在现代西方人眼中,我们不是他们所说的社会主义,而是共产主义。对于这些过

保守主义与美国式自由的两篇演讲

保守主义与美国式自由的两篇演讲 哈维·曼斯菲尔德 Conservatism and American Freedom: Two Lecturers by Harvey C. Mansfield The Dilemma of Conservatism & Democratic Greatness in the Founding 关键词:保守主义 自由主义 自然权利 自私 低贱 伟大 个人主义 提 要:在这两篇演讲中,美国著名政治哲学家曼斯菲尔德从两个方面讨论了自由民主与保 守主义之间复杂的关系。在《保守主义的两难》中,作者指出,起源于法国大革命时的保守 主义是自由主义的小兄弟,针对自由主义的自私和低贱的两个欠缺,要么提出一套取而代之 的方案,要么弥补自由主义的不足。在作者看来,真正成熟的自由主义恰恰是认可自由主义 原则,弥补自由主义的不足,而不是取而代之。在《民主制伟大与美利坚之立国》中,作者 用美国政治史中的例子,来讨论“民主”和“伟大”之间的关系。美国第一次在一个大国实 现了民主,从而证明了民主与伟大之间并不是必然相排斥的。作者以此表明,现代的民主自 由不仅不排斥伟大的德性,而且要让两者相辅相成。 作 者:曼斯菲尔德(Harvey C. Mansfield),1932年生,美国哈佛大学政府学院讲座教授。 演讲一:保守主义的两难 何谓保守主义?我们很难给出一个放之四海而皆准的定义,即便在一时一地,例如当今美国,保守主义阵营内部各种力量也相互抵牾,例如坚持自由市场的自由至上论者(libertarians),力图维续国民道德的社会保守派,还有主张增强国防的新保守派,以及反感理性原则、坚持对传统美利坚民族(如果真有这回事的话)信念的传统保守派。 不过,我们还是不妨从一般的定性开始。保守主义是对自由主义的反动。尽管这一概念并不那么好界定,但自由主义的社会信条以权利为基础,进步则是其目标。作为对自由主义的反动,保守主义与自由主义彼此关联,它以自由主义为起点,是自由主义的小兄弟。“保守主义”这一术语出现在十九世纪,旨在反对法国大革命。无论从政治意义上还是哲学意义上,我们都应提到爱德蒙·伯克(Edmund Burke)的名字,伯克是法国大革命的第一个也是最伟大的反对者,他是第一位保守主义者,尽管他其实并未使用这个词。 保守主义反对自由主义,但究竟是在何种意义上呢?这里我们就遭遇到保守主义所面临的基本两难:保守主义是要提供一种自由主义的替代方案,抑或其使命只是在于纠正和弥补自由

民族主义与自由主义

(15分)17世纪以来,英国革命、美国革命和法国革命相继爆发,从中萌发的民族主义、自由主义和社会主义,对世界历史产生了极其重大的影响。阅读下列材料,回答问题。 材料一民族主义……在法国革命和拿破仑时期中得到了最大的促进。革命的领袖们为了从欧洲旧政权的猛攻中逃生.不得不动员国民军队——由乐于并渴望为祖国而战的、有政治觉悟的公民组成的军队……法国革命要求所有法国公民都说法语,它建立公立小学网,教授法语和灌输对国家的热爱。法国革命也促进了报纸、小册子和期刊的出现,粗浅通俗的读物给全国人民留下了深刻印象。法国革命还创立了像国旗、国歌和国家节日那样的民族主义仪式和象征。 ——摘自[美]斯塔夫里阿诺斯《全球通史》 材料二自由主义的兴起与资产阶级有密切关系……从其信条和支持者来说,它实质上是资产阶级的运动。自由主义学说在英国革命期间首次被明确地提出来,当时这些学说的主要内容是反对王室任意干涉宗教信仰自由、人身安全和财产安全……自由主义随着美国革命而得到进一步的解释和应用……美国革命在确立立宪政体方面取得很大进展……法国革命比美国革命更进步,它的《人权与公民权宣言》(即《人权宣言》)是18世纪自由主义的典范陈述。 材料三自由主义强调个人和个人权利,社会主义则强调社会和社会的集体福利……显然,包括社会主义和共产主义的马克思主义今天已经成为世界事务中的一支主要力量,其推动力和普遍的吸引力而言,可与民族主义相匹敌。 (1)据材料一,归纳法国革命从哪些方面促进了民族主义? (3分)结合所学知识指出,为什么说拿破仑战争的失败与民族主义思想意识的扩散息息相关?(2分) (2)结合英国革命爆发的原因说明当时自由主义学说的主要内容是反对王室任意干涉宗教信仰自由、人身安全和财产安全。(2分)结合所学知识指出美国革命在确立立宪政体方面取得怎样的进展?(1分)为什么说《人权与公民权宣言》是自由主义的典范陈述?(2分) (3)据所学知识指出,为什么说社会主义运动的发展是资本主义发展的产物?(1分)根据中国近代从维新变法的实践到马克思主义的广泛传播的有关史实,分析社会主义思想为中国先进知识分子接受的原因。(2分)结合建设有中国特色社会主义的实践活动,说明社会主义就其推动力和普遍的吸引力而言,可与民族主义相匹敌。(2分) [解析】 (1)①组成为祖国而战的国民军队。教授法语灌输对国家的热爱。出版报刊,传播民族主义思想。创立象征国家的仪式。②拿破仑后期进行的战争,侵犯了许多欧洲民族国家的主权,掠夺各国人民,促使欧洲各国民族主义萌发。 (2)①斯图亚特王朝实行宗教专制,迫害清教徒。厉行君主专制,触犯资产阶级利益。②根据三权分立原则把国家职权分为立法、司法和行政三个部门。(3人权宣言宣称人类生来是而且始终是自由平等的,自由、财产、安全和反抗压迫是不可动摇的人权。(学生答出任一点或回答“揭示了天赋人权、自由、平等的原则”均给满分)法律是公共意志的表现,在法律面前人人平等。(学生回答“否定封建等级制度”也给满分)私有财产是神圣不可侵犯的权利。 (3)①资本主义发展使资本主义制度的基本矛盾日益暴露,工人为改变自身的劳动状况和生活状况,开展多种斗争。②资产阶级维新派企图建立资本主义君主立宪制度,戊戌变法的失败证明,资产阶级改良道路在半封建的中国行不通。辛亥革命建立起资产阶级共和国,但随后北洋军阀独裁统治,帝国主义侵略加深,资产阶级民主共和无法救国。十月社会主义革命给中国送来了马克思主义,先进的中国人接受和传播社会主义思想,作为拯救国家、改造社会的思想武器。③只要能从中国特色社会主义建设成就方面说明在全球范围内对发展中国家具有吸引力即可给分。

石元康:自由主义与现代社会

自由主义与现代社会 石元康 《开放时代》2003年第1期 [内容提要]自由主义是现代社会的最基本的意识型态,它为现代社会及国家的正当性提供基础。没有任何其它的理论在现代社会享有这样尊崇的地位。虽然自由主义不断地受到批评,但是没有人可以想象有别的理论,可以取代它在现代社会中的地位。 Abstract: Liberalism is the fundamental ideology that lays the legitimate foundation for modern society and state. No other systems of ideology are on a par with it. Though being challenged constantly, it remains as the governing principle in modern society that is not to be replaced by any other theory. 一、世界解魅与现代社会 社会是一个由个体组成的统一体。每个统一体都有它的基本组织原则。现代西方社会的基本组织原则的根据是自由主义;我们可以说,自由主义是现代社会的基本哲学。如果翻阅一下历史,我们可以更进一步指出,在古代世界中,无论是中、西,自由主义的思想体系都没有出现过。中、西古代社会的基本组织原则都不是由自由主义所提供。儒家、亚理士多德的理论以及基督教这些古代的哲学及宗教体系,不仅不是自由主义式的理论,它们在最根本的地方还与自由主义的基本论点是背道而驰的。现代世界究竟有些甚么特点,使得它需要自由主义这个崭新的哲学作为它的组织原则? 韦伯对于现代性的研究将现代化的历史过程描述为理性化(rationalization)。他把这种理性的结构以及它如何在西方现代文化的观念及建制中体现出来作了详细的说明。韦伯所说的这种理性是工具——目的理性(means-end rationality)。在他的有名的《作者导言》(Author's Introduction)中,韦伯列举了工具理性在科学、经济、法律、建筑、宗教、音乐等方面的成就以及它们所显现的特性。①工具理性的特色是它只能提供达成某个目的的手段,对于目的来说,理性没有能力对它进行任何判断。这也就是休姆在更早的时候所提出的理性只是爱好(passion)的奴隶。在决定目的时,人所能凭借的只有爱好,当目的被选定之后,理性才能施展它选取手段的能力。② 理性之所以会工具化,是由于宇宙观的改变所引起的。这种宇宙观的改变是由亚理士多德式的目的性的宇宙观转变为现代科学所体现的机械式的宇宙观。韦伯将这个过程称之为世界的解魅(disenchantment of the world)。解魅的意义也就是休姆所说的事实与价值在逻辑上的隔绝。③在目的论的宇宙观中,价值及意义是客观地存在世界中的东西,因此,它们具有客观性。价值由于是宇宙构成的一部份,人们要获得价值所采取的办法是去发现它。我们对价值的认识也就构成了知识。由于世界本身就具有价值,因此,它也就构成了一个意义的网络。要对世界有所了解,必须把捉到它的意义。解魅之后的宇宙观,把价值与意义从世界中驱赶出去,世界只是由因果律将事态(states of af-fairs)连接起来。对客观的认识只是对事实世界的描述及说明。由于世界中并不包含意义及价值,因此,它们的来源只能是由人类的主

评述西方自由主义

评述西方自由主义思想 自由主义是一种意识形态、哲学,以自由作为主要政治价值的一系列思想流派的集合。广义的自由主义追求保护个人思想自由的社会、以法律限制政府对权力的运用、保障自由贸易的观念、支持私人企业的市场经济、透明的政治体制以保障少数人的权利。 一、西方自由主义的起源 自由主义作为一种意识形态,最早可以追溯至欧洲文艺复兴时期人文主义对国教权威的对抗。人文主义的主要思想是主张个性解放,重视人的作用,反对中世纪的摧残人的禁欲主义和宗教观;提倡科学文化,反对蒙昧主义,摆脱教会对人们思想的束缚;肯定人权,反对神权,摒弃作为神学和经院哲学基础的一切权威和传统教条。所以在文艺复兴时期人们就开始以各种艺术形式来表现自由和追求自由。而自由主义作为一种理论、一种完整的思想体系最早出现在英国,确切的讲是17世纪的英国资产阶级革命前后。 二、西方自由主义的类别 自由主义的分类有多种多样,有的把自由主义分为积极自由主义和消极自由主义,有的把自由主义分为大陆自由主义和英美自由主义,有的把自由主义分为经济自由主义,政治自由主义,伦理自由主义和哲理自由主义。虽然对自由主义的分类很多,而

且也有助于从不同角度来研究自由主义的思想,但目前我们国内对西方自由主义的分类主要倾向于分为西方经济自由主义和政治自由主义。经济自由主义是随资本主义经济发展而发展的,政治自由主义表现在积极的政治行动上,“如起草宪法和权利法案,建立代议制政府,推广制衡制度,编制法典等,最高主权被认为属于人民全体,政治制度则必须顺应人们的意志”,其中的代表人物是亚当斯密,马歇尔,还有哈耶克。政治自由主义作为一种政治哲学和思想流派,代表人物主要有托马斯·霍布斯,约翰·洛克等。 三、西方自由主义的内涵 自由主义所说的自由首先是政治和法律意义上的自由,这包括个人在生活、言论、结社、从事经济和社会活动上的选择权,自由的制度表现为开放的选择余地,而不自由的制度则尽量限制公民个人的选择度。自由也是哲学和审美层次上的,只是其诠释决不限于黑格尔式的思辨,把自由仅归结为对必然的了解和把握。因为自由主义者所强调的哲学意义上的自由仍然与其本义相关,从经验主义的意义上说,即使个人完全掌握了事物的全部必然性(事实上不可能),他仍然拥有选择权,必然性其实不是一条单行线,而是多条叉路口。头脑清醒而又乐观的人不会选择从悬崖上跳下去寻死,但他上山的道路却有多种选择,并不总是只有一条出路。而在审美上的自由权则显得更为广泛,“情人眼里出西施”便说明了审美的主观性,尽管人们的审美存在统计的共同

从自由主义和社会主义的起源来看二者之间的关系

从自由主义和社会主义的起源及其在 现实国家中的运用来看二者之间的关系 【摘要】改革开放以来,关于自由主义和社会主义关系的探讨在中国重新兴起。本文结合国内外学者的观点,探讨自由主义和社会主义产生的历史背景及其在现实国家中的应用,以此来阐述两者的关系。自由主义与社会主义不存在根本的不可调和的矛盾,没有自由主义因素的社会主义不是好的社会主义,而没有社会主义因素的自由主义也不是好的自由主义。 【关键词】自由主义;社会主义;关系 一、关于自由主义和社会主义关系的一些观点: 对自由主义和社会主义关系研究的角度不同,得出的结论也不相同。本文只择一些与本文相关的观点。 1.弗朗西斯·福山在1989年夏为《国家利益》杂志攥写的一篇题为“历史的终结”的文章中认为,自由民主制度也许是“人类意识形态发展的终点”和“人类最后一种统治形式”,并因此构成“历史的终结”。换句话说,在他看来,苏联解体、东欧剧变标志着自由主义的胜利、社会主义的失败。历史终结于资本主义,意识形态终结于自由主义。很明显,福山是将自由主义和社会主义作为两大对立派来看待的,认为两者水火不容,不可能共存。 2.台湾学者朱高正所持观点与福山相反。在朱高正看来,所谓现代化是一个完整的概念,其实质性的涵义在于自由主义与社会主义

的对立与互动。首先,从理念角度讲,自由主义的核心理念是自由,而社会主义的核心理念是平等。朱高正认为不能偏向任何一方,若一方压倒另一方,都会给彼此带来伤害,如同经济上的公平和效率一样。明智的做法是保持一种必要的张力,寻找一种动态的平衡。其次从现实实践看,斯大林的社会主义模式的失败,其原因是对自由主义采取一刀两断的措施,完全拒绝自由主义对社会主义进行必要的补充。而西欧北美的资本主义之所以垂而不死,仍然焕发出强大的生命力,正是其在一定程度上采纳了社会主义的因素。如德国的社会市场经济、法国的左右两党的折衷共治以及美国的“新政”。他认为这些国家的现代化模式虽然以自由主义标榜,但实际上却是自由主义与社会主义两者之间的对峙与对话的互动发展。同时他也认为,中国特色的社会主义市场经济,同时也是自由和平等的有机结合、社会主义与市场经济的良性互动。 3.童世骏教授在《对社会主义与自由主义之争的新考察——当代西方左翼思想家的社会主义观给我们的一些启发》一文中,对西方左翼思想家将社会主义和自由主义结合起来的观点进行了研究。他讲道:“在当代西方许多左翼思想家当中,…社会主义?的观念与…市场经济一法治国家?和…市民社会?的结合,不仅是可能的,而且是必要的。”他在详细介绍了他们的相关论述后,还讨论了自由主义和社会主义的重要思想观念——自由和平等的关系。他说:“如果说自由主义的重点是…消极自由?的话,那么社会主义的重点不妨说是…积极自由?”,他还讲自由主义追求的是形式平等,而社会主义是在追求实质平等。

自由主义在中国

自由主义在中国 引言 自由主义是一种意识形态、哲学,以自由作为主要政治价值的一系列思想流派的集合。其特色为追求发展、相信人类善良本性、以及拥护个人自治权,此外亦主张放宽及免除专制政权对个人的控制。更广泛的,自由主义追求保护个人思想自由的社会、以法律限制政府对权力的运用、保障自由贸易的观念、支持私人企业的市场经济、透明的政治体制以保障每一个公民的权利。在现代社会,自由主义者支持以共和制或君主立宪制为架构的自由民主制,有着开放而公平的选举制度,使所有公民都有相等的权利参与政治。【1】 自由主义是一种政治哲学也是一种建立在自由与平等之上的世界观。前者是强调古典自由主义而后者更为明显的是在强调社会自由主义。自由主义者广泛支持的观点如言论自由、新闻自由、宗教自由、自由市场、民权、民主社会、世俗政府、国际合作等等,通常取决于他们对于自由主义原则的认识。 19世纪自由主义政府成立于欧洲国家,以及南美和北美。在这一时期,古典自由主义在意识形态方面的主要对手是保守主义,但随后自由主义又面临着在意识形态方面新的对手的挑战,如法西斯主义和共产主义。20世纪后,在欧洲和北美,建立福利国家成为自由主义扩张的新的组成部分。 中国作为社会主义国家,在1978年改革开放引进市场经济模式后,也不得不面对自由主义所带来的问题与借鉴意义。 关键词: 自由主义中国转型市场经济新自由主义 正文: 早在古希腊时期,人们就已经明确表达了个人的自由理想。18世纪亚当·斯密《国富论》的出版,标志着近代自由主义的发端。从20世纪80年代开始,自

由主义的状况发生了悄悄的变化。发生这种变化的原因在于:以保守主义思想为指导的社会改革虽然取得了一定的成效,但是却无力从根本上解决资本主义发展的问题。在主要的西方国家,福利国家政策令人们失望,人们对自由主义的主张也丧失了信心,而且代之而起的“经济复兴计划”也未能尽如人意,保守主义的主张同样引起人们的怀疑。【2】 在1978年到1988年之间的十年时间里,英国政府面对自己所产生的独特的社会经济问题进行了一系列的努力,采取了一系列诸如缩减政府编制,对原有的税制进行改革,将部分国营企业私有化、控制货币供应量、削减福利开支和增加工人工资等措施。这一些列措施所产生的效果保证了英国在相当一段时间内的经济增长率稳定在3%左右。但是经济发展的同时,失业率也不断的增长,而且人与人之间、地区之间的贫富差距更是相对的扩大了,对于这种情况,英国政府也只能加强国家对于经济的干预,增加货币供应,同时降低存款利率,以这样的方法来遏制经济下滑的趋势。 美国政府在1982年之前也是坚定不移的一直执行着保守主义的经济政策,尽量减少国家对经济的干预,但是在保守主义政策的大背景下,各个领域不断浮现的社会经济问题不断的质疑着美国政府所采取保守主义政策的正确性。终于美国政府在1982年“中期选举”之后不得不增强了对经济生活的干预【3】,其具体措施跟英国几乎如出一辙,而且与英国相比较来说,美国的国会在政府开展干预行动的同时也是不断的通过相关的法案,以此来支持美国政府在此种情况下作出的干预行动。 在20世纪80年代中期,由英国著名经济学家凯恩斯【4】提出的凯恩斯主义开始兴起,凯恩斯从当时西方资本主义国家所面临的主要问题入手,着重分析了资本主义国家普遍产生经济危机、以及失业率增高面临严重失业危机的原因。由于对于这些问题所做出的分析比较准确且提出了一系列相应的解决办法,凯恩斯主义逐渐被资本主义国家所普遍接受,在20世纪90年代,逐渐成为了比较主流的指导理论。而且凯恩斯主义中要在自由放任的政府和过度干预的政府之间寻找一条新的道路的主旨,也与20世纪80年代中期以后自由主义的基本主张不谋而合。 综上,自由主义在20世纪末的振兴是经过一系列西方资本主义历史阶段的选择与沉淀的结果,与此同时,自由主义自身的理论也得到了丰富和发展。而且,随着自由主义指导下的西方资本主义重新焕发生机,自由主义自身也变得更加充满了活力。 自由主义作为西方的主流思潮之一,早在20世纪初就被引入了中国,但是当时的中国深陷战争的泥潭,对于自由主义的讨论就变得不再具有那么大的现实

自由主义发展

澄清被混用的新自由主义 ----兼谈对New Liberalism和Neo-Liberalism的翻 译 李小科 (中共中央党校哲学部) [提要] 在英文中,New Liberalism和Neo-Liberalism 代表两个有着截然不同的主张和诉求的思想流派,且本来分属政治哲学和经济学两个不同的学科语境。由于它们都被翻译成“新自由主义”,当前国内学术普遍在批判Neo-Liberalism时,导致批判本身的错位和人们对New Liberalism的很大误解。将New Liberalism译为“新自由主义”,Neo-Liberalism统一译为“‘新’自由主义”或“新古典自由主义”有利于正本清源,促进学术对话。 [关键词] 自由主义古典自由主义新自由主义新古典自由主义 在过去的一年多时间里,大陆各类报刊刊登了大量批判新自由主义的文章和著作。就文章而言,笔者在今年4月底利用CNKI数字图书馆进行的一次“新自由主义”检索表明,2003-2004年大陆公开发表的各类批判性文章中,以“新自由主义”为题的有117篇,

其中92篇为2004年发表;以“新自由主义”为关键词进行讨论的文章有97篇,其中62篇为2004年发表。在此期间,出版的批判性著作有《新自由主义评析》(社会文献出版社2004)、《新自由主义思潮》(高等教育出版社2004)和《全球化与新自由主义》(广西师范大学出版社2003)等。正为因为如此,有的学者称2004年为中国大陆的“新自由主义”批判年。 权威专家和媒体对“新自由主义”的协同批判,已给许多人留下了深刻的印象。不过,我们在批判各自所理解的新自由主义的时候,许多人似乎并没有太多考虑作为汉语的“新自由主义”一词所蕴涵的另外一层意思。因为,英文中的New Liberalism和Neo-Liberalism(另拼为Neoliberalism)往往都被人们译成“新自由主义”,[1-p53]而这两种“主义”却恰好指的是在二十世纪西方社会中并存和争执着的、有着相反诉求的两股不同思想流派。更有甚者,有的研究完全依据中译本,并不清楚有New Liberalism和Neo-Liberalism之分,以至于将自己批判的Neoliberalism意义上的新自由主义,“望文生义”地标注为New Liberalism[2-p11]1。 另外,此前刊载在在国内哲学权威刊物《哲学研究》和《哲学动态》上的相关文章,在使用“新自由主义”一词的时候,也没有大注意这二者之间的细分和差异,即将原本属于New Liberalism一方的罗尔斯、德沃金与属于Neo-Liberalism一脉的哈耶克、弗里

浅谈自由主义与社会契约论

浅谈自由主义与社会契约论 自由主义,是西方社会最重要的政治价值观念。自由主义政治思潮的发展经历了传统自由主义和现代自由主义两个历史时期。 自由主义作为一种理论、一种完整的思想体系最早出现在英国,确切地讲是17世纪的英国资产阶级革命前后。在这一时期,伴随着一批思想家,如霍布斯和洛克等关于天赋人权、契约论、自然法学说的提出,个人自由在历史上第一次被作为社会等价物优先于社会价值来讨论,并把对个人自由的维护作为出发点,寻求国家的起源,政治治理的基本原则以及相应的制度的安排,从而形成近代完整的自由主义体系内容。第一次对自由主义做出系统哲学表述的是托马斯·霍布斯。他的学说对近代自由主义的最大贡献在于其个人主义内涵,标志着与柏拉图、亚里士多德哲学以及中世纪神学的决裂。在他看来,国家并非先验存在的,更不是道德实体,它只不过是每个人为保证各自的权利不被侵犯而组成的人造物,同时也是人们实现各自利益的工具,个人的权利是第一位的,而国家和社会次之。 但是,只要以人类社会整体存在的方式发展,就不得不以一种更高的权威来维护社会稳定和秩序,这就是国家主权。然而,国家是由契约产生的,缔结契约的同时人们表达了服从的意愿。这种服从并不是一时冲动产生的,是通过权衡利弊之后才做出的决定。虽然这时的霍布斯还没能够提出自由的结论,个人的自由没有保留到社会状态中去,但为洛克的自由主义理论奠定了坚实的基础。自由主义的核心要素被提炼为一整套知识传统,

并通过一个强有力的政治运动表达出来,是在英国内战期间以及光荣革命之后的执政时期。其最重要的代表是约翰·洛克,洛克对自由主义的贡献主要在于他的学说奠定了自由主义理论的两大基石:其一是个人自然权利的理论,其二是政府必须基于被统治者同意的理论。在英国政治传统中,洛克一直被认为是为光荣革命辩护的重要思想家,其理论对美国革命与立宪产生了巨大的影响。洛克政治理论的出发点与霍布斯相似,即从自然状态出发构建合理的政治秩序,自然状态是一种无政府状态。洛克笔下的自然状态一方面可以被理解为历史上或现实中实际存在的状态。洛克曾举美国的印第安人作为这种状态的例证。但更为重要的是,自然状态是一种哲学家的理论构想。哲学家希望探讨政府的目的、形式等问题。为了回答这些问题,他们便提出一个理论预设:假如没有政府人们会处于何种状态,会过一种什么样的生活?当代著名保守主义哲学家诺齐克在构建政治理论时,也是从讨论无政府状态下个人的权利以及个人生活的不便开始,从而进一步推导出最小政府的结论。 洛克的理论在历史上产生过重大影响。在英国政治传统中,洛克一直被认为是为光荣革命辩护的重要思想家。近年来,这一说法受到一些挑战。但至少有一点是不容质疑的,洛克的理论是对光荣革命后确立的立宪政体的最好阐释之一。洛克的理论对美国革命与立宪产生了巨大的影响,这几乎是学术界一致公认的。十八世纪,自由主义的大本营在法国,当时的法国是欧洲思想最活跃、创造力最丰富的地方。这一时期在历史上又被称为启蒙时期,代表人物主要有:孟德斯鸠、卢梭、贡斯当和托克维尔。这些思想家所关注的问题涉及到今天自由主义讨论的核心问题。

浅析变迁视角下的自由主义与保守主义

浅析变迁视角下的自由主义与保守主义 对新自由主义和新保守主义的变迁过程进行梳理有助于在其对话过程中理解新保守主义的政策主张从何而来,因何而起。从新保守主义对新自由主义批评的理论出发点和实际运行的过程分析后,以期对新保守主义做简要的评述。 标签:新自由主义;新保守主义;批评 自由主义与保守主义是西方主要思想流派的中坚力量,其百年的思想流变过程,既是二者的互动也是二者对现实的回应。以变迁的视角去考察和审视这一历史过程,在动态角度中评述二者发展与当代表现,对理解西方资本主义世界制度和思想的变化都有所帮助。 一、极盛而衰的自由主义与新保守主义 (一)二战后的繁荣与新自由主义 自由主义作为西方工业资本主义的主要思想流派、政治哲学和意识形态,已有几百年的历史。随着资本主义的发展,自由主义也几经调整和改造其主张,以19世纪末20世纪初为分界点,划分为古典自由主义和现代自由主义或新自由主义。20世纪的自由主义继承和发展了古典自由主义的传统,保持着自由主义的基本特征,如个人主义原则、理性主义、社会进步的观念。约翰·格雷认为“自由主义的第一个特征是个人主义,他宣告对任何社会集体的否定,将个人独立的精神置于首位;第二个特征是平等主义;第三个特征是普遍主义;第四个特征是社会的向善主义”[1]。这四个特征说明古典自由主义与现代自由主义是一脉相承又与时俱进的。当然传统自由主义与现代自由主义还是有着很大的区别的,最主要的区别表现为:传统自由主义坚持消极自由及在其基础上的最小国家原则,而现代新自由主义以积极自由为出发点,坚持主张积极政府,期待政府在社会经济事务中发挥重要的作用。 这种积极自由基础上的现代自由主义兴起于20世纪初,在威尔逊总统的“新自由运动”和罗斯福”新政”时期得到了迅速发展,二战后达到了顶峰。在理论上,为其辩护的理论家主要有霍布豪斯、霍布森、凯恩斯及二战后美国著名政治哲学家罗尔斯,其《正义论》的问世,标志着20世纪自由主义进入了其发展的巅峰。在实践上,西方各国都以现代自由主义为理论指导制定各种政策,美国约翰逊总统“伟大社会”的提出及施行,标志着新自由主义在实践上的最高峰。 然而,当新自由主義在理论上与实践上达到其顶峰之后,其衰落也是必然的。这是因为新自由主义不可能在理论上和实践上解决西方社会的根本矛盾和问题。20世纪60年代开始,战后最严重的经济危机在整个西方社会爆发,出现了通货膨胀与经济停滞并存及“滞胀”现象,引发了一连串新的社会矛盾。在理论上,保守主义、社会主义、货币主义理论派别对其群起而攻之;在实践上,民权运动、学生运动、女权运动、反战运动风起云涌,使奉行新自由主义的政府彻底束手无

社会民主主义与自由主义的比较

社会民主主义与自由主义的比较 [摘要] 文章以瑞典和美国为例探讨不同意识形态政党对西方福利制度改革和“福利国家”发展的影响。认为不同性质的执政党具有不同的价值观,代表不同的阶级、阶层的利益,其价值理念必然会影响国家政策的制定和实施,也必定会影响国家模式的构建。我们必须认清现象背后的本质,避免被表面的东西所迷惑,不顾本国的实际盲目崇拜西方。同时,应该以马克思主义的科学态度看待自由主义和社会民主主义在提高国家福利、实现社会和谐发展方面的具体方法和措施,善于吸收和借鉴其中科学合理的成份,为我所用。[关键词] 社会民主主义自由主义福利国家瑞典美国“福利国家”是在资本主义市场经济发展下产生的国家类型,通常包括混合经济、充分就业、收入均等、社会福利和社会保障等内容在内的一系列政策目标,其主旨在于通过政府的干预和调节,尽量消除资本主义社会的失业、贫困和不公平等问题,以使资本主义制度趋向更为稳定和合理。在西方,社会福利问题历来是各党派之间激烈争论的重大问题。不同的政党和政治力量对“福利国家”的态度和主张有所不同,它们之中的任何一个政党上台执政,都必然会推行自己的政策主张,因而不同政党、不同政治力量的发展变化无疑会对福利经济制度的改革及“福利国家”

的发展方向产生影响。一社会民主主义是100多年来西方社会主义的主要形态,这是一种温和的、议会制的社会改良主义,它是欧洲各国工人阶级社会党、社会民主党、工党的政治意识形态。其思想渊源可以上溯到19世纪初的空想社会主义,以及后来的英国宪章派、法国的小资产阶级社会主义、德国的拉萨尔主义等形形色色的社会主义流派。它们依靠国家帮助实现社会主义的观点,对社会民主主义的形成有着极大的影响。同时,自由主义的自由与宪政思想,对社会民主主义也有重要影响。[ 1 ] 民主与改良是社会民主主义的基本理念,1951年的《法兰克福宣言》将民主社会主义确立为社会党国际的纲领目标。这一目标经过曲折发展的过程最终形成自由、公正、互助的基本价值观。这种价值观是社会民主党的执政理念产生的哲学基础,对国家福利制度的改革和福利国家的发展方向具有重要的指导作用。首先,强调平等的生活机会和全面的社会保障。在社会民主党要建立与完善的民主社会主义的三项基本价值中,自由是处于第一位的,但这一自由观有别于资本主义的自由主义,它强调的是人的全面发展的自由和参与社会和政治的自由,而不是摆脱外在的束缚和限制。正如《柏林纲领》所指出的,社会民主党谋求建立这样一种社会:在这个社会里,每个人都能自由地发展自己的个性,并能负责地参加政治、经济与文化生活。而这种自由要求能够摆

相关文档
最新文档