AND THE SYMMETRIC IMPRIMITIVITY THEOREM
基于马克思主义哲学视角的有神论分析

Advances in Philosophy 哲学进展, 2023, 12(2), 317-322 Published Online February 2023 in Hans. https:///journal/acpp https:///10.12677/acpp.2023.122056基于马克思主义哲学视角的有神论分析罗章松青海民族大学马克思主义学院,青海 西宁收稿日期:2023年1月6日;录用日期:2023年1月26日;发布日期:2023年2月7日摘要 马克思主义无神论是认识和改造世界的科学理论和思想武器,用马克思主义的基本观点和方法来分析有神论,从唯物主义的视角看待非唯物主义,有利于进一步推进马克思主义的传播,推进马克思主义的大众化,从而让人们树立正确的世界观和价值观。
从马克思主义哲学出发,站在物质与意识的辩证关系及社会存在与社会意识的辩证关系的角度对有神论进行分析,从认识论上阐明有神论的现实根源,从而对有神论进行反驳,对巩固马克思主义主流意识形态阵地、发展社会主义先进文化、加强无神论宣传教育等方面都具有重要的现实意义。
关键词无神论,有神论,物质,意识Analysis of Theism from a Marxist PerspectiveZhangsong LuoSchool of Marxism, Qinghai Nationalities University, Xining Qinghai Received: Jan. 6th , 2023; accepted: Jan. 26th , 2023; published: Feb. 7th , 2023AbstractMarxist atheism is a scientific theory and ideological weapon for understanding and transforming the world. Analyzing theism with the basic viewpoints and methods of Marxism and viewing non- materialism from the perspective of materialism is conducive to furthering the spread of Marxism and the popularization of Marxism, so that people can establish correct worldviews and values. Analyzing theism from the perspective of the dialectical relationship between matter and con-sciousness and the dialectical relationship between social existence and social consciousness from the perspective of Marxist philosophy, clarifying the realistic roots of theism from the epistemo-罗章松logical point of view, and thus refuting theism, is of great practical significance in consolidating the mainstream ideological position of Marxism, developing advanced socialist culture, and streng-thening atheistic propaganda and education.KeywordsAtheism, Theism, Matter, Consciousness Array Copyright © 2023 by author(s) and Hans Publishers Inc.This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution International License (CC BY 4.0)./licenses/by/4.0/1. 引言无神论是伴随着有神论而产生,并在同有神论的斗争中不断发展壮大而来的[1]。
【杂】聊聊我的男神:JordanPeterson

【杂】聊聊我的男神:JordanPeterson这篇⽂章我打算聊聊我的男神Jordan Peterson(简称JP)。
如果还不太了解JP,那么下⾯两个链接是JP的背景介绍:最开始接触到JP,是逛B站的时候看到了JP关于⼥权的视频:当时就被JP的理性和逻辑所折服了,后⾯了解了⼀下JP,发现他的三个⼯作都⾮常值得深⼊研究:直接看原⽂⽐较吃⼒的同学,可以直接看这两个资源:感兴趣的同学,建议直接听JP的这个演讲:读这本书第⼀个收获是:缓解了个⼈的焦虑。
毫不夸张地说,在汉语世界⾥,很多⽂字⼯作者(写⽂章的)以解构焦虑为名,⾏助长焦虑之实,操纵⼤众⼼理,挣点击量的钱。
我觉得这种⾏为与吃⼈⾎馒头相⽐,没有什么本质区别。
这些⽂字⼯作者,通过助长问题的扩⼤,没有任何实质性的⼯作,更别提创造出了什么价值。
这本书则不同,除了提出问题,JP还提出了解决问题的⽅案,这绝对不是最好的⽅案,但是有⽅案总⽐没有⽅案,继续焦虑要好得多。
关于对抗焦虑的⼯作,在这⾥不展开,之后单独写⼀篇⽂章。
读这本书第⼆个收获是:深刻地认识到了学会讲故事的重要性。
这也直接引导我去读接下来要介绍的MoM,以及之前在看纪录⽚了解到的另⼀本书:读这本书第三个收获是:认识到⾯对⼀个问题,特别是没有固定答案的问题,认识问题的⾓度和分析问题的⽅法,⽐问题本⾝更重要。
其实这12条法则,并不是什么新鲜事物,但是JP认识问题和解释这12条法则的视⾓和⽅式,让没有什么见识的我感觉到⽿⽬⼀新。
关于阅读姿势,个⼈推荐的还是直接阅读书本原⽂。
因为JP是通过讲故事来讲道理,也可能是东西⽅思维⽅式的不同,所以初读这本书感觉有点啰嗦,⽽且特别催眠(因为是睡前读的)。
那为什么还要读这本书呢?我⽤JP的⼀段视频来回答:下⾯是关于这本书(同样也是⼀门课程)的介绍和资料:这本书可以说是JP思想的基⽯,下⾯摘⼀段⾖瓣书评:为什么这本书还没被翻译成中⽂? Peterson教授是个天才。
刚刚上完了Peterson在多伦多⼤学的PSY434课,这是必读的⼀本书。
Lin Shu’s translation of Uncle Tom’s Cabin林纾对汤姆叔叔的小屋的翻译赏析

Some Key Concepts of Gadamer’s Philosophical Hermeneutics
1. The Historicality of Understanding and Pre-understanding
According to Gadamer (1999: 249-252), pre-understanding belongs to historical reality and is produced by tradition. We were born and brought up in tradition which is a mode of thought or behavior engraved in us. Tradition influences us and vice versa. But our own relatively stable surroundings and accumulated experience make us insensitive or even blind to situations. In the case of translators, they live in their particular historical period. They may belong to different social systems and cultural systems, and differ in life experience, language competence, writing style and so on. Namely, all kinds of factors, objective and subjective, have already “stand there” and are bound to contribute to the different understanding and interpretation of the text.
莱布尼茨人类理智新论英文的言语

莱布尼茨人类理智新论英文的言语Ludwig van Leibniz: The Human Rationality Revisited in English。
In the annals of philosophical inquiry, the name of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz stands as a beacon of rationality, his thoughts echoing through the centuries in the language of reason. Born in 1646, the German philosopher's "Human Rationality: A New Perspective" continues to resonate with scholars and thinkers, offering a unique lens through which we understand the nature of human cognition.Leibniz's work, initially published in Latin, sought to refine and expand upon the principles of rationality that had been laid out by his contemporaries, particularly RenéDescartes. His "New Theory" was not just a philosophical treatise, but a synthesis of mathematics, metaphysics, and epistemology, all grounded in the belief that human reason is inherently perfectible.At the heart of Leibniz's argument lies the concept of "the calculus of ideas," a method that he believed facilitated the efficient processing and comparison of thoughts. He argued that our rationality lies not in the absolute certainty of every belief, but in the ability to refine and revise our ideas in light of evidence and reason. This dynamic, he proposed, is what drives progress and intellectual growth.In English, Leibniz's ideas are often translated as "the principle of sufficient reason," which asserts that every event or fact must have a cause or explanation. This principle, he believed, is the bedrock of human rationality, as it encourages us to seek understanding and to question the foundations of our beliefs. It is this constant quest for explanation that drives us to reason and innovate.Leibniz's emphasis on the interplay between mind and nature, as well as his belief in the harmony of the universe, also informs his understanding of human rationality. He saw reason as a cosmic force, not just a cognitive faculty, and believed that it was through reason that we could harmonize with the world around us.However, his views were not without criticism. Critics, like David Hume, challenged the idea of innate knowledge and the absolute certainty of reason. Leibniz, in response,辩称 that while our initial knowledge may be uncertain, it could be refined through a process of continuous reasoning.In conclusion, Leibniz's Human Rationality, as translated into English, remains a testament to the power of reason and the ongoing quest for understanding. His ideas continue to inspire philosophical debates and shape the way we think about the limits and potential of human cognition. As we delve into his works, we are reminded that the pursuit of rationality is not a static endeavor, but a dynamic process that evolves with the human spirit.This document, written in the spirit of Leibniz's own philosophical inquiry, aims to capture the essence of his rationality theory and its enduring influence in the English language. It serves as a reminder that, despite the passage of time, the quest for wisdom and reason remains a fundamental aspect of human nature.。
科技的哲学名词解释

科技的哲学名词解释Science and technology have greatly shaped the world we live in today. The rapid advancement of technology has not only revolutionized our daily lives, but also influenced the way we think about and understand the world around us. In this article, we will explore and explain some key philosophical concepts related to science and technology without delving into politics.1. EmpiricismEmpiricism is a philosophical concept that emphasizes the importance of sensory experience and observation in acquiring knowledge. According to empiricists, our understanding of the world is derived from our perceptions and experiences. In the context of science and technology, empiricism forms the foundation for the scientific method. Scientists rely on empirical evidence to validate their hypotheses and theories, ensuring that their claims are based on observable and measurable data.2. RationalismIn contrast to empiricism, rationalism places greater importance on reason and logical deduction in the acquisition of knowledge. Rationalists argue that reason and innate ideas play a crucial role in understanding the world. While empirical evidence is essential in scientific inquiry, rationalists believe that reason and logic can also provide insights that cannot be derived solely from sensory experience. In the realm of technology, rationalism is often employed in the design and development of complex systems, where logical analysis is used to build reliable and efficient solutions.3. Technological DeterminismTechnological determinism is a philosophical concept that posits that technology is the primary driver of social, cultural, and economic changes in society. According to this perspective, technology shapes the way we think, act, and even govern ourselves. Technological determinists argue that technology has its own autonomous development and that societal changes occur in response to new and emerging technologies. Thisconcept challenges the traditional view that society solely determines the direction of technological development.4. Ethical AIArtificial intelligence (AI) has become a prominent field in recent years, sparking debates about its ethical implications. Ethical AI refers to the moral considerations and principles that guide the development and use of AI systems. As AI becomes more sophisticated and autonomous, questions arise regarding the responsibility and accountability of AI systems. Ethical AI aims to ensure that AI systems are designed and used in ways that align with societal values and respect for human rights, while also considering issues such as fairness, transparency, and privacy.5. Digital DivideThe digital divide is a term used to describe the gap between individuals and communities who have access to modern information and communication technologies (ICTs) and those who do not. It reflects the unequal distribution of technological resources across different regions and populations. The digital divide encompasses multiple dimensions, including access to the internet, computer literacy, and affordability of ICTs. Bridging the digital divide has become an important goal to ensure equal opportunities for individuals and promote inclusive development in an increasingly digitalized world.6. Technological SingularityTechnological singularity is a concept that explores the hypothetical future scenario where artificial general intelligence surpasses human intelligence and triggers runaway technological growth. This concept highlights the potential exponential growth in technology that could lead to radical changes in society. Some argue that technological singularity may lead to unprecedented advancements, while others express concerns about the implications and control of such a powerful intelligence. The idea of technological singularity raises deep philosophical questions about the nature of intelligence, consciousness, and humanity's place in the universe.In conclusion, science and technology are not only practical fields but also give rise to profound philosophical questions. Concepts such as empiricism, rationalism, technological determinism, ethical AI, the digital divide, and technological singularity provide a glimpse into the complex relationship between humanity, knowledge, and technology. Understanding these philosophical underpinnings helps us navigate the ever-changing technological landscape and engage in meaningful discussions about the impact of science and technology on society.。
实践论 中英文对照

实践论中英文对照Pragmatism is a philosophical tradition that originated in the United States in the late 19th century. It emphasizes the practical consequences of beliefs and actions, rejecting the idea that truth is fixed and unaffected by human experience. 实践论是一个起源于19世纪末的美国哲学传统。
它强调信仰和行动的实际后果,拒绝了真理是固定不受人类经验影响的观念。
One of the key figures in the development of pragmatism was William James, whose work emphasized the importance of individual experience and the need for beliefs to be tested in the real world. Another influential thinker in this tradition was John Dewey, who believed that philosophy should be concerned with practical problems and the improvement of society. 实践论发展中的重要人物之一是威廉·詹姆斯,他的作品强调个人经验的重要性,以及信仰在现实世界中需要得到验证的必要性。
另一个具有影响力的思想家是约翰·杜威,他认为哲学应该关注实际问题和社会的改善。
Pragmatism challenges traditional philosophical theories that prioritize abstract principles or metaphysical concepts. Instead, itfocuses on the practical implications of beliefs and ideas, asking whether they are useful in achieving desired outcomes. This emphasis on utility and practicality sets pragmatism apart from more abstract and theoretical approaches to philosophy. 实践论挑战传统的哲学理论,这些理论优先考虑抽象原则或形而上学概念。
库恩在科学哲学中首次使用了“范式”(paradigm)术语吗

库恩在科学哲学中首次使用了“范式”(paradigm)术语吗?10年前,我发表了一篇论文《库恩在科学哲学中首次使用了“不可通约的”术语吗?》。
在那篇论文中,我对所提出的问题做了否定性的回答。
因为爱因斯坦在1946年撰写、1949年发表的“自述”中,马赫在1905年出版的《认识与谬误》、可能在1895/1896年的系列讲演“探究的心理学和逻辑”中,都曾经在科学哲学的意义上使用了“不可通约的”(incommensurable,inkommensurabler)术语――先于库恩1962年出版的《科学革命的结构》。
在本文,我拟通过手头的资料论证,库恩也不是在科学哲学(和科学社会学)的意义上首次使用“范式”(paradigm)术语的人。
众所周知,库恩的“范式”概念是《科学革命的结构》的中心概念,其内涵十分丰赡,据说他的这一概念在书中至少有21种用法。
范式是科学活动的实体,是库恩科学观的核心概念。
范式是由理论要素、心理要素以及联结这两个要素的本体论和方法论要素组成的。
理论要素包括概念、原理、定律、公式、实验技术和设备等;心理要素包括科学家团体从事科学活动的共同心理功能,诸如信念、直觉、审美、灵感、顿悟、价值判断等;本体论、方法论要素起着世界观、思维方式、研究纲领的作用,以此指导科学共同体的工作。
不用说,英语中的“范式”(paradigm)一词源远流长。
据1999年出版的《梅里亚姆-韦伯斯特新学院词典》第九版(Merriam-Webster’s New Collegiate Dictionary, Ninth Edition)解释,paradigm出自晚期拉丁语paradigma,而后者来自希腊语paradeigma,15世纪进入英语语汇。
paradigm其意有三:1)范例、样式,尤其是特别清楚或典型的例子和原型;2)表示一个词在它的所有变化中的变格或变位;3)科学学派或学科的哲学框架或理论框架,在这个框架内,理论、定律、概括以及为支持它们而做的实验被系统地阐述。
Symmetries in QFT

Dφ φ (x1 ) ...φ (xn ) exp i
(−1) G (x1 , ..., x2 )
n 1 (−1) Z n 1 (−1) Z n
Dφ′ φ′ (x1 ) ...φ′ (xn ) exp i dD x L (φ′ ) Dφ φ (x1 ) ...φ (xn ) exp i dD x L (φ)and QED. 4.1 One Loop Correction to the Photon Propagator. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 4.2 4.3 Resummation of loops. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The Electron Self Energy and the Vertex Function. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
5
Anomalies. 5.1 5.2 5.3 Chiral Symmetry . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . The ABJ Anomaly. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Fujikawa’s Method for determining the Chiral Anomaly. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
- 1、下载文档前请自行甄别文档内容的完整性,平台不提供额外的编辑、内容补充、找答案等附加服务。
- 2、"仅部分预览"的文档,不可在线预览部分如存在完整性等问题,可反馈申请退款(可完整预览的文档不适用该条件!)。
- 3、如文档侵犯您的权益,请联系客服反馈,我们会尽快为您处理(人工客服工作时间:9:00-18:30)。
TRANSACTIONS OF THEAMERICAN MATHEMATICAL SOCIETYVolume 352,Number 10,Pages 4759–4787S 0002-9947(00)02618-0Article electronically published on June 14,2000AN EQUIV ARIANT BRAUER SEMIGROUPAND THE SYMMETRIC IMPRIMITIVITY THEOREMASTRID AN HUEF,IAIN RAEBURN,AND DANA P.WILLIAMSAbstract.Suppose that (X,G )is a second countable locally compact trans-formation group.We let S G (X )denote the set of Morita equivalence classesof separable dynamical systems (A,G,α)where A is a C 0(X )-algebra andαis compatible with the given G -action on X .We prove that S G (X )is acommutative semigroup with identity with respect to the binary operation[A,G,α][B,G,β]=[A ⊗X B,G,α⊗X β]for an appropriately defined balancedtensor product on C 0(X )-algebras.If G and H act freely and properly on theleft and right of a space X ,then we prove that S G (X/H )and S H (G \X )areisomorphic as semigroups.If the isomorphism maps the class of (A,G,α)tothe class of (B,H,β),then A αG is Morita equivalent to B βH .1.IntroductionMackey’s imprimitivity theorem identifies the unitary representations U of a locally compact group G which have been induced from a closed subgroup H .In Rieffel’s formulation,it says that U is induced precisely when it is part of a covariant representation (π,U )of the dynamical system C 0(G/H ),G ;he proved the theorem by showing that the crossed product C 0(G/H ) G is Morita equivalent to the group C ∗-algebra C ∗(H )(and invented the C ∗-algebraic theory of Morita equivalence while he was at it).The symmetric imprimitivity theorem of Green and Rieffel involves commuting free and proper actions of two groups,G and H ,on a space X ,and asserts that C 0(G \X ) H is Morita equivalent to C 0(X/H ) G (see [26]);one recovers Mackey’s theorem by taking H ⊂G and X =G .In recent years we have studied dynamical systems involving continuous-trace C ∗-algebras (A,G,α)by viewing them as elements of an equivariant Brauer group Br G (X )associated to the induced action of a group G on the spectrum X of the algebra A [6],[18].Inspired by the symmetric imprimitivity theorem,it was shown in [16]that if H and G act freely and properly on X as above,then there is a group isomorphism λof Br H (G \X )onto Br G (X/H )such that B βG is Morita equiv-alent to A αH whenever (B,G,β)is a representative for λ(A,H,α).Green and Rieffel’s symmetric imprimitivity theorem is recovered by taking A =C 0(G \X );in general,this Morita equivalence can be obtained by applying the noncommuta-tive symmetric imprimitivity theorem of [21]to systems involving continuous-trace algebras.Our present goal is to find a version of the isomorphism of [16]which incorpo-rates as much algebraic structure as possible and yet gives the full strength of the4760ASTRID AN HUEF,IAIN RAEBURN,AND D.P.WILLIAMSsymmetric imprimitivity theorem as discussed in[21].We shall do this by intro-ducing an equivariant Brauer semigroup S G(X):the objects in S G(X)are againrepresented by systems(A,G,α),but now we insist only that A is a C0(X)-algebra in the sense of[14],[2],[17],and that the actionαis compatible with a given action of G on X and C0(X).This incorporates many more systems:the algebras A neednot be type I or even nuclear,and their spectrums could be much bigger than X. (For example,any algebra of the form C0(X,D)could arise.)We begin by introducing our Brauer semigroup S G(X).As in[6],the productis based on a balanced tensor product of the underlying algebras.Here,however, we want to allow non-nuclear algebras,and this leads to technical difficulties:toget an associative multiplication we have to use the maximal tensor product rather than the spatial one.The objects in S G(X)will be Morita equivalence classes of systems,and checking that these equivalences are compatible with our balancedtensor products requires some technical innovations.Our basic isomorphism is proved in section3.Specifically,we prove that if G and H are second countable locally compact groups acting freely and properly onthe left and right,respectively,of a second countable locally compact space X in such a way that(s·x)·h=s·(x·h),then there is a semigroup isomorphismθof S G(X/H)onto S H(G\X).We give an explicit description ofθin terms of Rieffel’s generalizedfixed-point algebras Aγfor proper actionsγ:G→Aut A. Every class in S G(X/H)has a representative of the form(Aβ,G,¯α),whereαandβare commuting proper actions of G and H,respectively,on a C0(X)-algebra A which are compatible with the given actions on X.Since Aβis a subalgebra of the multiplier algebra M(A),¯αis just the natural lift ofαto M(A).The isomorphismθmaps the class of(Aβ,G,¯α)to the class of(Aα,H,¯β).Furthermore,Aα ¯βH and Aβ ¯αG are Morita equivalent.The Morita equivalence can be proved two ways; since(A,G×H,α×β)defines a class in S G×H(X)and the actions of G and H are free and proper,the equivalence follows from Kasparov’s[14,Theorem3.15]or fromthe second author’s[21,Theorem1.1].Carefully untangling Kasparov’s argument leads to a tensor product imprimitivity bimodule,and also to an interesting result concerning regular representations of the crossed products Aα ¯βH arising in our theorem.(Recall that regular representations are faithful exactly when the reduced crossed product Aα ¯β,r H equals the universal crossed product Aα ¯βH.) We present our result on regular representations in section4.Given that the action of G on X is free and proper,α:G→Aut A must be proper and saturated in Rieffel’s sense and hence A0:=C c(X)·A can be completed to an A α,r G–Aα-imprimitivity bimodule Yαby[27,Theorem1.5].An important special case occurs when A=C0(X,D)andα=τ⊗γfor a C∗-dynamical systemγ:G→Aut D.It is proved in[23,Theorem2.1]that C c(X,D)can be completed to a C0(X,D) αG–Ind X G(A,α)-imprimitivity bimodule X.We prove that Yαis a quotient of X, and use this to prove that regular representations of A αG are faithful;thus, A α,r G=A αG.Furthermore,Yαadmits an H-action u such that(Yα,u) implements an equivalence between(A αG,H,β ι)and(Aα,H,¯β).Using[7], [5],we can form an A α×β(G×H)–Aα ¯βH-imprimitivity bimodule Yα u H based on C c(H,Yα).The set-up is symmetric in H and G,and the tensor product bimodule(1.1)W:=(Yβ v G) ⊗A α×β(G×H)(Yα u H)THE BRAUER SEMIGROUP 4761is an A β ¯αG –A α ¯βH -imprimitivity ing the symmetry in (1.1)and a result of Combes,we can prove that regular representations of A β ¯αG arefaithful if and only if regular representations of A α ¯βH are.This generalizes aresult of Quigg and Spielberg [20,Theorem 4.2].Although the approach leading to (1.1)was used in proving our generalization of Quigg-Spielberg,it is often convenient in applications (cf.[9])to have a more concrete realization of the imprimitivity bimodule.By appealing to [21],we canobtain an A β ¯αG –A α ¯βH -imprimitivity bimodule Z which is a quotient of the module constructed in [21,Theorem 1.1]based on C c (X,A ).It is natural to ask ifthe two modules are the same,and it turns out that they are isomorphic.We give a proof in the case A =C 0(X,D )at the end of section 4.Since Br G (X )is easily identified with a subgroup of the group S G (X )−1of invertible elements in S G (X ),our definitions and results concerning S G (X )extend those for the equivariant Brauer group Br G (X ).However,Br G (X )is actually equal to S G (X )−1,and we prove this in an appendix;the result and its proof are essentially due to Green [12],but were never published.2.Preliminaries2.1.C 0(X )-algebras.If X is a locally compact (Hausdorff)space,then a C 0(X )-algebra is a C ∗-algebra A together with a homomorphism ιA :C 0(X )→ZM (A )which is nondegenerate in the sense that ιA C 0(X ) ·A :=span {ιA (ϕ)·a :ϕ∈C 0(X )and a ∈A }is dense in A .There is already considerable literature on C 0(X )-algebras;in par-ticular,[3]and [17]give nice overall treatments.We recount some of the basic properties here for convenience.The Dauns-Hofmann Theorem identifies the center ZM (A )of the multiplier algebra with C b (Prim A ).It is not hard to see that if (A,ιA )is a C 0(X )-algebra,then there is a continuous map σA :Prim(A )→X such that ιA (ϕ)and ϕ◦σA are equal in ZM (A ).Conversely,if σA :Prim(A )→X is continuous,thenιA (ϕ)a :=(ϕ◦σA )·a for all ϕ∈C 0(X )and a ∈Aclearly defines a homomorphism ιA :C 0(X )→ZM (A ),and it is not hard to see that ιA is nondegenerate.When convenient,we can view σA as a continuous function on ˆA.We usually suppress the homomorphism ιA ,and write ϕ·a in place of ιA (ϕ)a and a ·ϕin place of aιA (ϕ).Thus a C 0(X )-algebra A is a central C 0(X )-bimodule.1Conversely,if A is a nondegenerate central C 0(X )-bimodule,then ιA (ϕ)a :=ϕ·a makes A into a C 0(X )-algebra provided (ϕ·a )∗=¯ϕ·a ∗for all a ∈A and ϕ∈C 0(X ).We will write C 0,x (X )for the ideal of functions in C 0(X )which vanish at x .If A is a C 0(X )-algebra,then let I x be the closed ideal1If X is a B -bimodule,we call X a central B -bimodule when b ·x =x ·b for all x ∈X and b ∈B .4762ASTRID AN HUEF,IAIN RAEBURN,AND D.P.WILLIAMSbe denoted by a (x ).Some of the basic properties of the “section”x →a (x )are summarized in the next lemma.Lemma 2.1([3],[17]).Suppose that A is a C 0(X )-algebra.(a)For all a ∈A ,the map x → a (x ) is upper semicontinuous.That is,{x ∈X : a (x ) ≥ }is closed for all ≥0.(b)The map x → a (x ) is continuous for all a ∈A if and only if σA is openfrom Prim(A )to X .(c)For all a ∈A , a =sup { a (x ) :x ∈X }.(d)If ϕ∈C 0(X )and a ∈A ,then (ϕ·a )(x )=ϕ(x )a (x ).2.2.Balanced tensor products.We will write S (X )for the collection of all separable C 0(X )-algebras.We want to define a C 0(X )-balanced tensor product on S (X )with the objective of defining,up to isomorphism,an associative operation on S (X )for which C 0(X )is an identity.Since S (X )can contain non-nuclear algebras,an approach based on identifying Prim(A ⊗B )with Prim(A )×Prim(B ),such as employed in [23,§1],is inadequate.However,Blanchard’s maximal C 0(X )-balanced tensor product is sufficient for our purposes [3],[2].(Blanchard considered only the case in which X is compact.However,his results extend easily to the general case.Additional details may be found in [11,§2].)Definition 2.2([11,Definition 2.3]).Let A and B be two C 0(X )-algebras and let I be the closed ideal of A ⊗max B generated by{a ·ϕ⊗b −a ⊗ϕ·b :a ∈A ,b ∈B ,ϕ∈C 0(X )}.Then A ⊗X B :=(A ⊗max B )/I ,equipped with the C 0(X )-action given on the images a ⊗X b of elementary tensors a ⊗b byϕ·(a ⊗X b )=ϕ·a ⊗X b =a ⊗X ϕ·b,is called the maximal C 0(X )-balanced tensor product of A and B .Remark 2.3.It is possible to form other balanced tensor products,but our choice of the maximal tensor product is not a random one.For example,it is observed in [2]that Blanchard’s minimal tensor product m C (X ),which is defined using the spatial tensor product,need not be associative.Such pathologies vanish when one of the factors is nuclear,and Definition 2.2gives the same balanced tensor product used in [23]when at least one of the algebras is nuclear.The universal property of the maximal tensor product implies that every rep-resentation of A ⊗X B is of the form πA ⊗πB ,where πA and πB are commutingrepresentations of A and B ,respectively,such that ¯πA |C 0(X )=¯πB |C 0(X )(cf.,[11,Remark 2.5(a)]).If A is both a C 0(X )-and a C 0(Y )-algebra,and C is a C 0(Y )-algebra,then A ⊗Y C is a C 0(X )-algebra in such a way thatϕ·(a ⊗Y c )=(ϕ·a )⊗Y c for ϕ∈C 0(X ).If πA and πC is a pair of commuting representations such that¯πA |C 0(Y )=¯πC |C 0(Y ),then the corresponding representation πA ⊗Y πC of A ⊗Y C satisfies(πA ⊗Y πC )¯|C 0(X )=¯πA |C 0(X ).THE BRAUER SEMIGROUP 4763Lemma 2.4.Suppose that X and Y are second countable locally compact Hausdorffspaces,and that p :X →Y is a continuous surjection.Let C ∈S (Y ),and A,B ∈S (X ).Viewing,as necessary,elements in S (X )as elements of S (Y )via composition with p ,there is an isomorphism Ψof (A ⊗X B )⊗Y C onto (A ⊗Y C )⊗X B such that Ψ (a ⊗X b )⊗Y c =(a ⊗Y c )⊗X b.Similarly,there are isomorphisms Ψ1:A ⊗X B →B ⊗X A and Ψ2:(A ⊗X B )⊗Y C →A ⊗X (B ⊗Y C )such that Ψ1(a ⊗X b )=b ⊗X a and Ψ2 (a ⊗X b )⊗Y c =a ⊗X (b ⊗Yc ).Proof.The idea is to show that the natural isomorphism of (A ⊗max B )⊗max C onto (A ⊗max C )⊗max B (e.g.,[25,Corollary B.29])matches up the kernels of the quotient maps q 1onto (A ⊗X B )⊗Y C and q 2onto (A ⊗Y C )⊗X B .The kernel of the quotient map (A ⊗X B )⊗max C →(A ⊗X B )⊗Y C is {ker(πA ⊗X πB )⊗πC :(πA ⊗X πB )¯◦p ∗=¯πC |C 0(Y )}.So ker q 1,which is the inverse image of this ideal in (A ⊗max B )⊗max C ,is {ker(πA ⊗πB )⊗πC :πA |C 0(X )=πB |C 0(X )and πA |C 0(X )◦p ∗=πC |C 0(Y )}.On the other hand,the kernel of the map (A ⊗Y C )⊗max B →(A ⊗Y C )⊗X B is{ker(πA ⊗Y πC )⊗πB :πA ⊗Y πC |C 0(X )=πB |C 0(X )}= {ker(πA ⊗Y πC )⊗πB :πA |C 0(X )=πB |C 0(X )}.Thusker q 2= {ker(πA ⊗πC )⊗πB :πA |C 0(X )◦p ∗=πC |C 0(Y )and πA |C 0(X )=πB |C 0(X )},and the assertions about Ψfollow.The arguments for Ψ1and Ψ2are similar.Corollary 2.5.The maximal C 0(X )-balanced tensor product is associative on S (X ).2.3.Induced algebras.Suppose that X is a free and proper left G -space and that (A,G,α)is a dynamical system.Then Ind X G (A,α)is the C ∗-subalgebra of C b (X,A )consisting of those functions f such that (a )f (s ·x )=αs f (x ) ,and (b )x → f (x ) defines an element of C 0(G \X ).When X is a right G -space,condition (a )is replaced by (a ) f (x ·s )=α−1sf (x ) .An important example occurs when G is a closed subgroup of a locally compact group H .If H is viewed as a right G -space,then Ind H G (A,α)was studied at length in [22].Furthermore,if γ=τ⊗αis the diagonal action of G on C 0(X,A ),given by γs (f )(x )=αs f (s −1·x ) ,(2.1)then Ind X G (A,α)is the algebra denoted by GC (X,A )γin [23,§2]and by Ind(A ;X,G,α)or Ind(α)in [21].4764ASTRID AN HUEF,IAIN RAEBURN,AND D.P.WILLIAMS2.4.Proper actions on C∗-algebras.It is well-known that proper group actions on spaces—and therefore on abelian C∗-algebras—play a central rˆo le in the theory of crossed products.It is natural to try to extend the notion of proper actions to nonabelian C∗-algebras.Although it is not yet clear what the best definition of such an action should be,the notion developed by Rieffel in[27]is sufficient for our purposes.2Let(A,G,α)be a dynamical system,and suppose that A0is a denseα-invariant∗-subalgebra of A.A multiplier T∈M(A)belongs to M(A0)if T maps A0into itself.Since eachαs extends to an automorphism¯αs of M(A),we can consider the∗-subalgebra M(A0)αof¯α-invariant elements in M(A0). Definition2.6([27,Definition1.2]).A dynamical system(A,G,α)is called proper if there is a denseα-invariant∗-subalgebra A0of A such thata,b (s):=∆G(s)−1(a)for all a,b∈A0,the functions s→E2Rieffel has recently introduced a more general notion of properness for actions of locally compact groups on C∗-algebras[28].However,the earlier version suffices for our purposes here, and the newer notion is not(yet)associated with a general Morita equivalence result.THE BRAUER SEMIGROUP 47652.5.The Brauer Semigroup.Let (G,X )be a second countable locally compact transformation group.We consider the class S G (X )of pairs (A,α)where A is a C 0(X )-algebra and α:G →Aut A is a strongly continuous action which preserves the given G -action on X in thatαs (ϕ·a )=τs (ϕ)·αs (a )for all ϕ∈C 0(X ),s ∈G ,and a ∈A .(2.2)Alternatively,we can replace (2.2)with σA (s ·π)=s ·σA (π)for all π∈ˆA.Elements of S G (X )were called G -C 0(X )-algebras in [14].Example 2.9(Example 2.8continued).The action ϕ·f =(ϕ⊗1)f makes C 0(X,D )a C 0(X )-algebra,and C 0(X,D ),τ⊗α ∈S G (X ).Recall that two systems (A,G,α)and (B,G,β)are Morita equivalent if there is an A –B -imprimitivity bimodule X and a strongly continuous action u of G on X by linear maps such that for all x,y ∈X and s ∈G ,A u s (x ),u s (y ) =αs A x ,y ,and u s (x ),u s (y ) B =βs x ,y B .Suppose that (A,α)and (B,β)are elements in S G (X )which are Morita equivalent via (X ,u ).The actions of A and B extend to the respective multiplier algebras.Hence X becomes a C 0(X )–C 0(X )-bimodule.If h X :Prim B →Prim A is the Rieffel homeomorphism induced by X ,and if we use the Dauns-Hofmann Theorem to identify ιA (f )with f ◦σA and ιB (f )with f ◦σB ,then it is not hard to see that(f ◦σA )·x =x ·(f ◦σB ◦h X )(cf.,[25,Proposition 5.7(a)]).It follows that we have ιA (f )·x =x ·ιB (f )for all x ∈X and f ∈C 0(X )exactly when the diagramPrim B σB H H H H H H H H H h X4766ASTRID AN HUEF,IAIN RAEBURN,AND D.P.WILLIAMSNow suppose that (A,α)and (B,β)belong to S G (X ).Then s →αs ⊗βs is a strongly continuous automorphism group of A ⊗max B ,and for all a ∈A ,b ∈B ,and ϕ∈C 0(X ),αs ⊗βs (ϕ·a ⊗b −a ⊗ϕ·b )=τs (ϕ)·a ⊗b −a ⊗τs (ϕ)·b.(2.4)It follows that each αs ⊗βs preserves the balancing ideal,and defines an automor-phism αs ⊗X βs of A ⊗X β.It is not hard to check that s →αs ⊗X βs is strongly continuous and equivariant;that is,(A ⊗X B,α⊗X β)∈S G (X ).Suppose that X is an A –C -imprimitivity bimodule and that Y is a B –D -im-primitivity bimodule.Then the algebraic tensor product X Y has a completion X ⊗max Y which is an A ⊗max B –C ⊗max D -imprimitivity bimodule in the expected way.Although a sketch of this is given in [4,Proposition 2.9],we provide a proof for convenience.Lemma 2.14.Suppose that A ,B ,C ,and D are C ∗-algebras,that X is an A –C -imprimitivity bimodule,and that Y is a B –D -imprimitivity bimodule.Then Z :=X Y is an A B –C D -bimodule,and there are unique A B -and C D -valued pre-inner products on Z such thatA ⊗maxB x ⊗y ,z ⊗w =A x ,z ⊗By ,w , x ⊗y ,z ⊗w C ⊗max D = x ,z C ⊗ y ,w D.With these inner products,Z becomes an A B –C D -pre-imprimitivity bimod-ule with respect to the maximal tensor product norms on A B and C D .The completion X ⊗max Y is an A ⊗max B –C ⊗max D -imprimitivity bimodule.Proof.Exactly as in the proof of [25,Proposition 3.36],Z is easily seen to satisfy properties (a),(b),and (d)for a pre-imprimitivity bimodule as laid out in [25,Definition 3.9].The issue is to show that the inner products are bounded;that is,we need to show thatν·α,ν·α C D ≤ ν 2A ⊗max B α,α C D ,and (2.5)A B α·µ,α·µ ≤ µ 2C ⊗max D A B α,α ,(2.6)for all α∈X Y ,µ∈C D ,and ν∈A B .(We have decorated the inner products with the algebraic tensor products to emphasize that we are working on the incomplete bimodule X Y .)Let X ⊗max Y be the completion of X Y as a right Hilbert C ⊗max D -module (see [25,Lemma 2.16]).Let q :X Y →X ⊗max Y be the natural map.Weclaim that there is a homomorphism ΦA of M (A )into L (X ⊗max Y )such that ΦA (m ) q (x ⊗y ) =q (m ·x ⊗y ).Since ΦA (m ∗)will act as an adjoint for ΦA (m ),it will suffice to see that ΦA (m )is bounded on X Y with respect to · X ⊗max Y .Since M (A )is spanned by its unitary elements,we can assume that m is unitary.THE BRAUER SEMIGROUP 4767If α= ni =1x i ⊗y i ,then ΦA (m )q (α) 2X ⊗max Y := ΦA (m )q (α),ΦA (m )q (α) C D= n i,j =1 m ·x i ,m ·x j C ⊗ y i ,y j D= ni,j =1 x i ,x j C ⊗ y i ,y j D= q (α) 2X ⊗max Y ;this proves the claim.Thus we obtain commuting homomorphisms ΦA :A →L (X ⊗max Y )and ΦB :B →L (X ⊗max Y )such that ΦA (a )q (x ⊗y )=q (a ·x ⊗y )and ΦB (b )q (x ⊗y )=q (x ⊗b ·y ).The universal property of the maximal tensor product guarantees that there is a homomorphism ΦA ⊗max ΦB of A ⊗max B into L (X ⊗max Y ).But ν·α,ν·α C D = q (ν·α),q (ν·α) C ⊗max D = ΦA ⊗max ΦB (ν)q (α),ΦA ⊗max ΦB (ν)q (α) C ⊗max D ≤ ΦA ⊗max ΦB (ν) 2 q (α),q (α) C ⊗max D≤ ν 2A ⊗max B α,α C D .This establishes (2.5),and (2.6)is proved similarly;there is a homomorphism ΨC ⊗max ΨD of C ⊗max D into the adjointable operators on the completion of X Y as a left Hilbert A ⊗max B -module.(Once we establish both (2.5)and (2.6),so that we know Z is a pre-imprimitivity bimodule,then it follows that the two completions of X Y are the same.)The following lemma is a straightforward generalization of [6,Lemmas 2.1and3.2].Lemma 2.15.Suppose that A,B,C,D ∈S (X ),that X is an A –C -imprimitiv-ity bimodule over X ,and that Y is a B –D -imprimitivity bimodule over X .Then the Rieffel correspondence [25,Proposition 3.24]between ideals in C ⊗max D and A ⊗max B induced by X ⊗max Y maps the balancing ideal J X of C ⊗max D to the balancing ideal I X in A ⊗max B .In particular,the quotient X ⊗X Y of X ⊗max Y is an A ⊗X B –C ⊗X D -imprimitivity bimodule over X .Thus,if (A,α)∼(C,γ)and (B,β)∼(D,δ)in S (X ),then (A ⊗X B,α⊗X β)∼(C ⊗X D,γ⊗X δ).Proposition 2.16.The binary operation[A,α][B,β]:=[A ⊗X B,α⊗X β]is well-defined on S G (X ),and with respect to this operation,S G (X )is a commuta-tive semigroup with identity equal to the class of C 0(X ),τ .Proof.The operation is well-defined in view of Lemma 2.15.It is associative and commutative by Lemma 2.4since the isomorphisms there are easily seen to be equivariant.The map ϕ⊗a →ϕ·a extends to a well-defined C 0(X )-isomorphism of C 0(X )⊗X A onto A ,and the final assertion follows from this.4768ASTRID AN HUEF,IAIN RAEBURN,AND D.P.WILLIAMS3.The Main TheoremTheorem3.1.Suppose that G and H are second countable locally compact groups acting freely and properly on the left and right,respectively,of a second countable locally compact space X in such a way that(s·x)·h=s·(x·h).Then there is a semigroup isomorphismθ:S G(X/H)→S H(G\X)(3.1)such that if[B,β]=θ([A,α]),then A αG is Morita equivalent to B βH.Indeed, every class in S G(X/H)has the form[Aβ,¯α]for some(A,α×β)∈S G×H(X),andthen we haveθ[Aβ,¯α]=[Aα,¯β]so that Aβ ¯αG is Morita equivalent to Aα ¯βH.Remark3.2.In the next section,we will give another proof of the Morita equiv-alence of Aβ ¯αG and Aα ¯βH which implies both are Morita equivalent to A α×β(G×H).Lemma3.3.Suppose that A is a C0(X)-algebra.Then the mapϕ⊗a→ϕ·a ex-tends to a homomorphismΦof C0(X,A)onto A which satisfiesΦ(f)(x)=f(x)(x) for all x∈X and f∈C0(X,A).The homomorphismΦintertwines the action ϕ·f:=(ϕ⊗1)f of C0(X)on C0(X,A)with the given action on A.Proof.The map(ϕ,a)→ϕ·a is bilinear,and hence induces a linear mapΦon the algebraic tensor product C0(X) A,which is easily seen to be a∗-homomorphism. Letπbe a faithful representation of A.Because the range ofι:C0(X)→M(A) lies in ZM(A),the representationsπand¯π◦ιhave commuting ranges,and hence induce a representation(¯π◦ι)⊗maxπof C0(X)⊗max A.Sinceπis faithful,it is isometric,and we haveΦi ϕi⊗a i=iϕi·a i=πiϕi·a i=i¯π◦ι(ϕi)π(a i)=(¯π◦ι)⊗maxπiϕi⊗a i≤iϕi⊗a imax;thusΦis norm-decreasing and extends to a homomorphism on all of C0(X)⊗max A. We obtain the required mapΦby identifying C0(X)⊗max A with C0(X,A)(cf., e.g.,[25,Propositions B.43and B.16]).For an elementary tensor f:=ϕ⊗a,the formulaΦ(f)(x)=f(x)(x)follows from the identity(ϕ·a)(x)=ϕ(x)a(x)(Lemma2.1(d)),and this extends to general f∈C0(X,A)by linearity and continuity.Thefinal remark is trivially true for f∈C0(X) A,and also extends to f∈C0(X,A)by linearity and continuity. Proposition3.4.Suppose G acts freely and properly on X and(A,α)∈S G(X). Then(A,α)is proper with respect to the subalgebraA0:=span{ϕ·a:ϕ∈C c(X)and a∈A}.THE BRAUER SEMIGROUP 4769We have to verify the hypotheses (a)and (b)of Definition 2.6.For each pair of generators ϕ·a and ψ·b ,we have (ϕ·a )αs (ψ·b )∗= ϕτs (¯ψ) · aαs (b )∗ .The function s →ϕτs (¯ψ)vanishes unless supp ϕ∩s ·(supp ψ)=∅,and hence has compact support because G acts properly on X .Thus both functions s →(ϕ·a )αs (ψ·b )∗and E ϕ·a ,ψ·b lie in L 1(G,A ),and (a)is satisfied.To verify (b),we need a lemma.Lemma 3.5.For each f ∈C c (X,A ),the function µ(f )(x ):=G τs ⊗αs (f )(x )ds = Gαs f (s −1·x ) ds belongs to Ind X G (A,α)⊂C b (X,A )⊂M C 0(X,A ) .The multiplier ¯Φ µ(f ) be-longs to M (A 0)α,depends only on the image Φ(f )of f in A ,and satisfies c ¯Φµ(f ) = G c αs Φ(f ) ds for c ∈A 0.(3.2)(In particular,the integrand on the right-hand side is a continuous function of compact support from X to A ,so the integral converges to an element of A .)Proof.That µ(f )∈Ind X G (A,α)is proved for elementary tensors f =ϕ⊗a in [25,Lemma 6.17],and the proof carries over almost verbatim.Since every multiplier m of A satisfies (ϕ·a )m =ϕ·(am )and m ·(ϕ·a )=ϕ·(ma )for ϕ∈C c (X )and a ∈A ,we trivially have ¯Φµ(f ) ∈M (A 0).We shall next verify (3.2).If c =ϕ·b ∈A 0,then (ϕ·b )¯Φµ(f ) =Φ(ϕ⊗b )¯Φ µ(f ) =Φ (ϕ⊗b )µ(f ) .Now, (ϕ⊗b )µ(f ) (x )= ϕ(x )bG αs f (s −1·x ) ds = Gϕ(x )b αs f (s −1·x ) ds.Because G acts properly on X ,s →(ϕ⊗b )(τs ⊗αs (f ))is a continuous function of compact support with values in C 0(X,A ),and hence the integral G (ϕ⊗b )τs ⊗αs (f )ds converges in C 0(X,A )in such a way that G (ϕ⊗b )τs ⊗αs (f )ds (x )= Gϕ(x )b αs f (s −1·x ) ds =(ϕ⊗b )µ(f )(x ).From the continuity of Φwe deduce that s →Φ (ϕ⊗b )τs ⊗αs (f ) =(ϕ·b )αs Φ(f )is a continuous function of compact support,and (ϕ·b )¯Φ µ(f ) =Φ (ϕ⊗b )µ(f ) =G Φ (ϕ⊗b )τs ⊗αs (f ) ds =G(ϕ·b )αs Φ(f ) ds,as claimed.4770ASTRID AN HUEF,IAIN RAEBURN,AND D.P.WILLIAMSThe formula (3.2)immediately implies that ¯Φ µ(f ) depends only on Φ(f ).To see that ¯Φ µ(f ) ∈M (A 0)α,we use that this integral formula converges in normin A :cαt ¯Φ µ(f ) =αt α−1t (c )¯Φ(µ(f )) =αtG α−1t (c )αs Φ(f ) ds =Gcαts Φ(f ) ds which is just c ¯Φµ(f ) by left-invariance of Haar measure.Proof of Proposition 3.4.Given ϕ·a and ψ·b in A 0,we define f ∈C c (X,A )by f (x )=span { ϕ·a ,ψ·b D:ϕ,ψ∈C c (X )and a,b ∈A }of M (A )α.The functions µ(f )for f :=¯ϕψ⊗a ∗b used to define ϕ·a ,ψ·b Dspan a C 0(G \X )-submodule M ofInd X G (A,α),which has the property that,for each a ∈A and x ∈X ,there exists g ∈M satisfying g (x )=a [25,Corollary 6.18].A partition of unity argument on G \X shows that M must therefore be dense in Ind X G (A,α).Thus the continuity of ¯Φimplies that it maps Ind X G (A,α)into A α.Further,since the image of M is by definition dense in A αand since ¯Φhas closed range,¯Φmaps Ind X G (A,α)onto A α.Thus:Proposition 3.6.Suppose G acts freely and properly on X and (A,α)∈S G (X ).Then the map Φof Lemma 3.3induces a homomorphism ¯Φof Ind X G (A,α)onto A α.Corollary 3.7.Suppose G ,H ,and X are as in Theorem 3.1,and (A,α×β)∈S G ×H (X ).Then (A α,¯β)∈S H (G \X )and ¯Φ:Ind X G (A,α)→A αis C 0(G \X )-linear.Proof.One can easily check that ϕ· x ,y D = ϕ·x ,y D when ϕ∈C 0(G \X ),so A αis a C 0(G \X )-submodule of M (A ).The action of C 0(G \X )on Ind X G (A,α)is nondegenerate,and ¯Φis easily seen to be C 0(G \X )-linear,so the action on A α=¯Φ Ind X G (A,α) is nondegenerate too.For ϕ⊗a ∈C c (X,A )we have Φ τH h⊗βh (ϕ⊗a ) =τH h (ϕ)·βh (a )=βh (ϕ·a )=βh Φ(ϕ⊗a ) ,so ¯Φintertwines the diagonal action of τH ⊗βon Ind X G(A,α)with the action of ¯βon A α.(We should write。