《公正:该如何做是好》:第一课
公正该如何做是好

公正该如何做是好?》观后感这门课的目的是唤醒无尽的求知和推理,看看它将我们带向何方。
MS 教授的《公正如何做是好的》,通过案例的方式引导我们进行批判性思考,颠覆了我们的即成观念,仿佛过去熟悉的事物一下子变得陌生,原来一切都不是理所当然。
通过《杀人的道德侧面》引出道德推理背后的观点,包括结果主义的道德推理和绝对主义的道德推理。
结果主义的道德推理:将行为的道德与否取决于该行为所产生的后果,即我们的行为对外界产生的影响。
结果主义的道德推理最有力的支撑即边沁的功利主义说(“最大幸福理论(成本效益理论)),:功利主义不考虑一个人的行为的动机和手段,仅考虑一个人的行为的结果对最大快乐值的影响。
”而绝对主义的道德推理则认为道德有其绝对的道德原则,有明确的责任和权利,而无论所造成的结果是怎样的。
代表人物康德。
在《给生命一个标签》和《如何衡量快乐》中,MS 教授提到了反对功利主义的两个观点:一是功利主义是否充分尊重了个体权利或少数群体的权利;二是能否将所有的价值转化成一个统一的价值尺度来度量。
基于对功利主义的批判,在《自由选择》和《我属于谁?》中自由主义发表了自己的观点:政府干预最少的社会是最理想的社会状态。
基于“我们是自己的主人”,反对家长式立法,道德立法以及税法。
而在《这片土地是我的土地》和《满合法年龄的成年人》中,洛克作为自由主义的修正者认为,在“自然状态”下,任何政治体制建立之前,每个人都享有生命自由和财产的自然权利。
然而,一旦我们同意进入社会,就同意了受法律制度约束。
通过《考虑你的动机》《道德的最高准则》以及《雇枪》,揭示了道德价值来源于出于义务的动机以及政治义务的源泉。
康德认为:赋予行为其道德价值的是动机,而且只有一种动机可以将道德价值加诸于行为,这就是出于义务的动机,只有出于义务的动机,而非基于偏好的动机,才是通往高尚品德的途径,只有在我基于义务而行动时,只有在我抗拒因偏好或自利之类的动机而行动时,甚至我也不因同情或者利他主义而行动时,只有这样,我的行为才是自由的;只有这样,我的行为才是自主的:只有这样,我的意志才不会被外在的因素所左右。
哈佛大学公开课:公正-该如何做是好?观后感

道德准则与差异选择人类对公平公正的追求从未停止,这段历史似乎一直与时代的发展同轴。
但伴随着岁月的打磨,社会的进步,人们对公平公正的关注点已经由对它的定义的探索,以及就某一事件而言的公平的转向为更具有同一性的哲学性研究。
在哈佛大学公开课:公正-该如何做是好?的讲述中,Sandel教授就公正、平等、民主与公民权利等社会基本问题,结合哲学理论所进行了引导性教学。
在这12个课时,24讲中,我们都不得不考虑一个问题——道德准则。
我们都知道,社会公平和正义,是以人的解放、人的自由平等权利的获得为前提的,是国家、社会应然的根本价值理念。
这一根本价值理念来是对现实生活中各类社会问题的普适性的归纳总结。
在第一课中,Sandel教授引用的几个案例是这样假设的:“你的电车飞速行驶,这时你发现轨道的尽头有五名工人正在施工,你的刹车失灵了。
如果没有立刻停车,这五名工人必死无疑。
这时你发现一条岔道,这条岔道的尽头只有一名工人在施工。
此时如果你愿意,你可以选择拧动方向盘,撞向那一名工人,但是保住了另外五名工人。
”这是一个极有争议的议题,因为无论我们选择了什么,或者做了些什么,都只是隐匿在现有道德准则下被道德左右而迷失进行了一场谋杀。
它成功的引发了我们的思考——为什么会有不同的选择?同样是牺牲一个人来拯救五个人,不同选择的道德原则是什么?或者说,价值判断的标准或者原则是什么?为什么就同一个问题而言,不同的角度下人们做出的选择都存在差异?而第一课第二讲《同类自残案》中, Sandel由第一个问题导入的思考介绍了功利主义哲学家Jeremy Bentham(杰瑞米·边沁)与19世纪的一个著名案例,此案涉及到的人是4个失事轮船的船员。
他们在海上迷失了19天之后,船长决定杀死机舱男孩,他是4个人中最弱小的,这样他们就可以靠他的血液和躯体维持生命。
可令他们没有想到的是,第二天,他们获救了。
这个案件引发了学生们对提倡幸福最大化的功利论的辩论,功利论的口号是“绝大多数人的最大利益”。
公正该如何做是好

《公正——该如何做是好?》JusticeWhat’s The Right Thing To Do?哲学就是让我们在面对自己熟知的事物时引导并且动摇我们原有的认知。
哲学让我们对熟知的事物感到陌生,不是通过提供新的信息,而是通过引导并激发我们用全新的方式看问题。
一旦所熟知的事物变得陌生,它将再也无法恢复到从前。
自我认知就像逝去的童真,不管你有多不安,你已经无法不去想或是充耳不闻了。
这一过程会充满挑战又引人入胜。
因为道德与政治哲学就好比一个故事,你不知道故事将会如何发展。
你只知道这个故事与你息息相关。
哲学将我们与习俗、既定假设以及原有信条相疏远。
这门课程旨在唤醒你们永不停息的理性思考,探索路在何方。
后果主义道德推理认为,是否道德取决于行为的后果,取决于你的行为对外界所造成的影响。
后果主义道德推理中最具影响的就是功利主义,由18世纪英国政治哲学家杰里米·边沁提出。
绝对主义道德推理认为,是否道德取决于特定的绝对道德准则,取决于绝对明确的义务与权利,而不管后果如何。
绝对主义道德推理中最为著名的则是18世纪德国哲学家伊曼努尔·康德。
杰里米·边沁的功利主义哲学其主要思想简单明了:不论个人还是政治道德,它的最高原则都是最大化公共福利、集体幸福,或者说幸福与痛苦的差额最大化。
一句话,效用最大化。
这就产生了绝大多数人的最大利益这条准则。
自由意志论自由意志论将个人权利看得很重。
之所以称为自由意志论是因为,这一理论认为个人的基本权利是人身自由权。
因为我们是独立的个体,所以我们无法提供任何社会需要或图谋的任何用途。
我们有自由选择的权利,按照自己意愿生活的权利,只要我们尊重他人的这一权利。
我们是自己的所有者或支配者。
约翰·斯图尔特·穆勒的功利主义哲学近代功利主义者约翰·斯图尔特·穆勒试图把功利主义人性化。
穆勒想要做到的是将功利主义演算放宽和修正,以容纳人道主义关切,比如对个体权利的尊重,以及对高级和低级快乐的区别对待。
《公正:该如何做是好》:第一课

杀人的道德侧面——公正该如何做是好

公正----该如何做是好第一讲:《杀人的道德侧面》这是一门讨论公正的课程,我们以一则故事作为引子,假设你是一名电车司机,你的电车以60英里/小时的速度,在轨道上飞驰,突然发现在轨道的尽头,有5名工人正在施工,你无法让电车停止下来,因为刹车坏了,你此时极度绝望,因为你深知,如果电车撞向那五名工人,他们全都会死,假设你对此确信无疑,你极为无助,直到你发现,在轨道的右侧,有一条侧轨,而在侧轨的尽头,有一名工人在那里施工,而你的方向盘还没有坏,只要你想,就可以把电车转到侧轨上去,牺牲一人挽救五人性命,下面是我们的第一个问题:何为正确的选择?换了你会怎样做?我们来做一个调查,有多少人会把电车开到侧轨上去?请举手…有多少人会让电车继续往前开?选择往前开的,请不要把手放下,只有少数人选择往前开,绝大多数都选择转弯。
我们先来听听大家的说法,探究一下为何,你们会认为这是正确的选择。
先从大多数选择了转向侧轨的同学开始,为何会这样选择?理由是什么?有没有自告奋勇的?你来站起来告诉大家。
A:“我认为当可以只牺牲一个人时,牺牲五人不是正确之举”当可以只牺牲一人时,牺牲五人不是正确之举…这理由不错,不错的理由。
还有其他人吗?人人都赞同这个理由?你来!B:“我认为这和9.11的时候是一种情况,那些让飞机在宾州坠毁的人被视为英雄,因为他们选择了牺牲自己,而不是让飞机撞向大楼牺牲更多人”,这么看来这条原则和9.11的是一样的,虽然是悲剧,但牺牲一人保全五人依然是更正确的选择,这就是大多数人选择把电车开上侧轨的理由吗,是吗?现在我们来听听少数派的意见,那些选择不转弯的。
你来~C:“我认为这与为种族灭绝以及极权主义正名,是同一种思维模式,为了一个种族能生存下来,以灭绝另一个种族为代价”,那换了是你在这种情况下会怎么做?为了避免骇人听闻的种族灭绝,你直接开上去把这五个人撞死吗?C:“大概会吧”真的会吗?C:“是的”,好吧,还有谁?(对C说)很有勇气的回答,谢谢,我们来考虑一下另一种情况的例子,看看你们,大多数的人,会不会继续坚持刚才的原则,即“牺牲一人保全五人是更好的选择”。
《公正该如何做是好》讲稿

《公正该如何做是好》讲稿###读书分享会各位领导,同事,大家上午好。
我是来自######。
很有幸参加这次读书分享会,今天,我给大家分享的书籍是《公正,该如何做是好》,这是一本以哲学理论为基础,讲述什么是公平,该如何做才能叫正义的书籍。
这本书的前身是哈佛大学的一门课程,图片左侧这位就是这门课程的教授—迈克尔・桑德尔,书籍是根据讲义改写出来的。
关于作者迈克尔·桑德尔教授,他首先是一位哲学家,其次是美国人文艺术与科学学院院士和哈佛大学政府系讲座教授,他的研究方向主要是当代西方社群主义,也就是相当于研究怎么让美国的社会更加和谐。
关于《公正:该如何做是好》这门课程,它是哈佛最受欢迎的课程,超过14000名学生修读,并创下哈佛单学期1115名学生选修记录,课程的目的是想要引导听众一起评判性思考关于公平、正义、民主与公民权利的一些基本问题。
桑德尔教授在12课时的讲授中,没有一味的讲理论,二是讲故事,提问题,然后在和学生的讨论中引出他想要讲的理论。
课程中出现了很多西方哲学史上的牛人,比如亚里士多德、边沁、密尔、洛克、康德。
课程中讨论的话题也是当代的一些热点话题,比如强制兵役制是否合理,高税收与高福利是否有利于社会发展,同性婚姻、代孕母亲这些与传统道德相违背的情况从法律的角度上看又是否可以是合法的。
在课程的第一讲中,桑德尔教授一上来就提出一个问题,假设你是一名电车司机,你的电车以60km\小时的速度在轨道上飞驰。
你突然发现在轨道的尽头有五名工人在施工,而你无法令电车停下来,因为刹车坏了。
此时你极度绝望,因为你深知如果电车撞向那五名工人,他们会全部死亡。
就在极为无助之时,你发现在轨道的右侧还有一条侧轨,而在侧轨的尽头,只有一名工人在那里施工,而你的方向盘并没有坏,只要你想,就可以把电车转到侧轨上去,牺牲一个人而挽救五个人,你会怎么做?这个选择是正确的吗?桑德尔教授要求所有人都做出自己的选择,并在课堂上做了一次简单的调查。
哈佛大学公开课《公正:该如何做是好》:第一课:英文字幕

Funding for this program is provided by...Additional funding provided by...This is a course about justice and we begin with a you're the driver of a trolley car, and your trolley car is hurtling down the trackat miles an hour. And at the end of the track you notice five workers working on the try to stop but you can't, your brakes don't feel desperate because you know that if you crash into these five workers, they will all 's assume you know that for so you feel helpless until you notice that there is, off to the right, a side track and at the endof that track, there is one worker working on the steering wheel works,so you can turn the trolley car,if you want to,onto the side trackkilling the one but sparing the 's our first question:what's the right thing to doWhat would you doLet's take a many would turnthe trolley caronto the side trackRaise your many wouldn'tHow many would go straight aheadKeep your hands up those of youwho would go straight handful of people would,the vast majority would 's hear first,now we need to beginto investigate the reasonswhy you thinkit's the right thing to 's begin with those in the majoritywho would turn to goonto the side would you do itWhat would be your reasonWho's willing to volunteer a reasonGo ahead. Stand it can't be rightto kill five peoplewhen you can onlykill one person wouldn't be rightto kill five if you could killone person 's a good 's a good elseDoes everybody agreewith that reason Go I was thinking it's the same reasonon / with regardto the people who flew the planeinto the Pennsylvania fieldas heroes because they choseto kill the people on the planeand not kill more peoplein big the principle therewas the same on /.It's a tragic circumstancebut better to kill oneso that five can live,is that the reasonmost of you had,those of youwho would turn YesLet's hear nowfrom those in the minority,those who wouldn't turn. , I think that'sthe same type of mentalitythat justifies genocideand order to saveone type of race,you wipe out the what would you doin this caseYou would, toavoidthe horrors of genocide,you would crashinto the five and kill themPresumably, would. Who elseThat's a brave 's consideranother trolley car caseand see whether those of youin the majoritywant to adhereto the principle"better that one should dieso that five should live."This time you're not the driverof the trolley car,you're an 're standing on a bridgeoverlooking a trolley car down the track comesa trolley car,at the end of the trackare five workers,the brakes don't work,the trolley caris about to careeninto the five and kill now, you're not the driver,you really feel helplessuntil you noticestanding next to you,leaning over the bridgeis a very fat you couldgive him a would fall over the bridgeonto the track right in the wayof the trolley would diebut he would spare the , how many would pushthe fat man over the bridgeRaise your many wouldn'tMost people wouldn''s the obvious became of the principle"better to save five liveseven if it means sacrificing one"What became of the principlethat almost everyone endorsedin the first caseI need to hear from someonewho was in the majorityin both do you explainthe difference between the two second one, I guess,involves an active choiceof pushing a person downwhich I guess that person himselfwould otherwise not have beeninvolved in the situation at so to choose on his behalf,I guess, to involve himin something that heotherwise would have escaped is,I guess, more than whatyou have in the first casewhere the three parties,the driver and the two sets of workers,are already, I guess,in the the guy working,the one on the trackoff to the side,he didn't chooseto sacrifice his life any morethan the fat man did, did heThat's true, but he wason the tracks and...This guy was on the ahead, you can come backif you want. All 's a hard question. You did did very 's a hard else can find a wayof reconciling the reactionof the majorityin these two cases , I guess in the first casewhere you have the one workerand the five,it's a choice between those twoand you have to makea certainchoice and peopleare going to diebecause of the trolley car,not necessarily becauseof your direct trolley car is a runaway thingand you're making a split second pushing the fat man overis an actual actof murder on your have control over thatwhereas you may not have controlover the trolley I think it's a slightlydifferent right, who has a replyThat's good. Who has a wayWho wants to replyIs that a way out of thisI don't think that'sa very good reasonbecause you choose to-either way you have to choosewho dies because you eitherchoose to turn and kill the person,which is an actof conscious thought to turn,or you choose to pushthe fat man overwhich is also an active,conscious either way,you're making a you want to replyI'm not really surethat that's the just still seemskind of act of actually pushingsomeone over onto the tracksand killing him,you are actually killing him 're pushing himwith your own 're pushing himand that's differentthan steering somethingthat is going to causedeath into know, it doesn't really sound rightsaying it , no. It's good. It's 's your name me ask you this question, standing on the bridgenext to the fat man,I didn't have to push him,suppose he was standing overa trap door that I could openby turning a steering wheel like you turnFor some reason,that still just seems more I mean, maybe if you accidentallylike leaned into the steering wheelor something like ... Or say thatthe car is hurtlingtowards a switchthat will drop the I could agree with 's all right. Fair still seems wrong in a waythat it doesn't seem wrongin the first case to turn, you in another way, I mean,in the first situationyou're involved directlywith the the second one,you're an onlooker as right. -So you have the choiceof becoming involved or notby pushing the fat right. Let's forget for the momentabout this 's 's imagine a different time you're a doctorin an emergency roomand six patientscome to 've been in a terribletrolley car of themsustain moderate injuries,one is severely injured,you could spendall daycaring for the oneseverely injured victimbut in that time,the five would you could look after the five,restore them to healthbut during that time,the one severely injured personwould many would save the fiveNow as the doctor,how many would save the oneVery few people,just a handful of reason, I life versus fiveNow consider another doctor time, you're a transplant surgeonand you have five patients,each in desperate needof an organ transplantin order to needs a heart,one a lung, one a kidney,one a liver,and the fifth a you have no organ are about to see them then it occurs to youthat in the next roomthere's a healthy guywho came in for a he's – you like that –and he's taking a nap,you could go in very quietly,yank out the five organs,that person would die,but you could save the many would do itAnyone How manyPut your hands upif you would do in the balconyI would Be careful,don't lean over too many wouldn'tAll right. What do you saySpeak up in the balcony,you who would yank outthe organs. WhyI'd actually like to explore aslightly alternate possibilityof just taking the oneof the five who needs an organwho dies first and usingtheir four healthy organsto save the other 's a pretty good 's a great ideaexcept for the factthat you just wreckedthe philosophical 's step back from these storiesand these argumentsto notice a couple of thingsabout the way the argumentshave begun to moral principleshave already begun to emergefrom the discussions we've let's considerwhat those moral principles look first moral principlethat emerged in the discussionsaid the right thing to do,the moral thing to dodepends on the consequencesthat will result from your the end of the day,better that five should liveeven if one must 's an exampleof consequentialist moral moral reasoninglocates moralityin the consequences of an act,in the state of the worldthat will result from the thing you then we went a little further,we considered those other casesand people weren't so sureabout consequentialist moral peoplehesitatedto push the fat manover the bridgeor to yank out the organsof the innocent patient,people gestured toward reasonshaving to do withthe intrinsic qualityof the act itself,consequences be what they were thought it was just wrong,categorically wrong,to kill a person,an innocent person,even for the sakeof saving five least people thoughtthat in the second versionof each story we this pointsto a second categorical wayof thinking about moral moral reasoninglocates moralityin certain absolutemoral requirements,certain categorical duties and rights,regardless of the 're going to explorein the days and weeks to comethe contrast betweenconsequentialist and categoricalmoral most influential exampleof consequential moral reasoningis utilitarianism,a doctrine inventedby Jeremy Bentham,the th centuryEnglish political most important philosopherof categorical moral reasoningis the th centuryGerman philosopher Immanuel we will lookat those two different modesof moral reasoning,assess them,and also consider you look at the syllabus,you'll notice that we reada number of greatand famous books,books by Aristotle, John Locke,Immanuel Kant, John Stewart Mill,and 'll notice toofrom the syllabusthat we don't onlyread these books;we also take up contemporary,political, and legal controversiesthat raise philosophical will debate equality and inequality,affirmative action, free speech versushate speech, same sex marriage,military conscription,a range of practical questions. WhyNot just to enliventhese abstract and distant booksbut to make clear,to bring out what's at stakein our everyday lives,including our political lives,for so we will read these booksand we will debate these issues,and we'll see how each informsand illuminates the may sound appealing enough,but here I have to issue a the warning is this,to read these booksin this way as an exercisein self knowledge,to read them in this waycarries certain risks,risks that are both personaland political,risksthat every studentof political philosophy has risks spring from the factthat philosophy teaches usand unsettles usby confronting us withwhat we already 's an difficulty of this courseconsists in the factthat it teacheswhat you already works by taking what we knowfrom familiar unquestioned settingsand making it 's how those examples worked,the hypotheticals with which we began,with their mix of playfulnessand 's also how thesephilosophical books estranges usfrom the familiar,not by supplying new informationbut by inviting and provokinga new way of seeing but,and here's the risk,once the familiar turns strange,it's never quite the same knowledge is like lost innocence,however unsettling you find it;it can never be un-thoughtor makes this enterprise difficultbut also rivetingis that moral and political philosophyis a story and you don't knowwhere the story will what you do knowis that the story is about are the personal what of the political risksOne way of introducing a courselike this would be to promise youthat by reading these booksand debating these issues,you will become a better,more responsible citizen;you will examine the presuppositionsof public policy,you will hone your political judgment,you will become a moreeffective participant in public this would be a partialand misleading philosophy,for the most part,hasn't worked that have to allow for the possibilitythat political philosophymay make you a worse citizenrather than a better oneor at least a worse citizenbefore it makes you a better one,and that's becausephilosophy is a distancing,even debilitating, you see this,going back to Socrates,there's a dialogue,the Gorgias, in whichone of Socrates' friends, Callicles,tries to talk him out tells Socrates"Philosophy is a pretty toyif one indulges in itwith moderationat the right time of life. But if onepursues it further than one should,it is absolute ruin.""Take my advice," Callicles says,"abandon the accomplishmentsof active life,take for your modelsnot those people whospendtheir time on these petty quibblesbut those who have a good livelihoodand reputation and manyother blessings."So Callicles is really saying to Socrates"Quit philosophizing, get real,go to business school."And Callicles did have a had a point because philosophydistances us from conventions,from established assumptions,and from settled are the risks,personal and in the faceof these risks,there is a characteristic name of the evasionis skepticism, it's the idea –well, it goes something like this –we didn't resolve once and for alleither the cases or the principleswe were arguing when we beganand if Aristotle and Lockeand Kant and Millhaven't solved these questionsafter all of these years,who are we to think that we,here in Sanders Theatre,over the course of a semester,can resolve themAnd so, maybe it's just a matterof each person having his or her ownprinciples and there's nothing moreto be said about it,no way of 's the evasion,the evasion of skepticism,to which I would offerthe following 's true, these questions have beendebated for a very long timebut the very factthat they have recurred and persistedmay suggest that thoughthey're impossible in one sense,they're unavoidable in the reason they're unavoidable,the reason they're inescapableis that we live some answerto these questions every skepticism, just throwing up your handsand giving up on moral reflectionis no Kant described very wellthe problem with skepticismwhen he wrote"Skepticism is a resting placefor human reason,where it can reflect uponits dogmatic wanderings,but it is no dwelling placefor permanent settlement.""Simply to acquiesce in skepticism,"Kant wrote,"can never suffice to overcomethe restlessness of reason."I've tried to suggestthrough these storiesand these argumentssome sense of the risksand temptations,of the perils and the would simply conclude by sayingthat the aim of this courseis to awaken the restlessness of reasonand to see where it might you very , in a situation thatdesperate,you have to dowhat you have to do to have to do what you have to doYou got to dowhat you got to do, pretty you've been going dayswithout any food, you know,someone just hasto take the has to make the sacrificeand people can , that's 's your name, what do you say to MarcusLast time,we started out last timewith some stories,with some moral dilemmasabout trolley carsand about doctorsand healthy patientsvulnerable to being victimsof organ noticed two thingsabout the arguments we had,one had to do with the waywe were began with our judgmentsin particular tried to articulate the reasonsor the principles lying behindour then confrontedwith a new case,we found ourselvesreexamining those principles,revising eachin the light of the we noticed thebuilt in pressureto try to bring into alignmentour judgmentsabout particular casesand the principleswe would endorseon also noticed somethingabout the substanceof the argumentsthat emerged from the noticed that sometimeswe were tempted to locatethe morality of an actin the consequences, in the results,in the state of the worldthat it brought we called thisconsequentialist moral we also noticedthat in some cases,we weren't swayedonly by the , many of us felt,that not just consequencesbut also the intrinsic qualityor characterof the act matters people arguedthat there are certain thingsthat are just categorically wrongeven if they bring abouta good result,even if they saved five peopleat the cost of one we contrasted consequentialistmoral principles with categorical and in the next few days,we will begin to examineone of the most influential versionsof consequentialist moral that's the philosophyof Bentham,the th centuryEnglish political philosophergave first the first clearsystematic expressionto the utilitarian moral Bentham's idea,his essential idea,is a very simple a lot of morallyintuitive appeal,Bentham's ideais the following,the right thing to do;the just thing to dois to maximize did he mean byutilityHe meant by utilitythe balance of pleasure over pain,happiness over 's how he arrivedat the principle of maximizing started out by observingthat all of us,all human beings are governedby two sovereign masters:pain and human beingslike pleasure and dislike so we should base morality,whether we're thinking aboutwhat to do in our own livesor whether as legislators or citizens,we're thinking aboutwhat the laws should right thing to do individuallyor collectively is to maximize,act in a way that maximizesthe overall level of 's utilitarianismis sometimes summed upwith the slogan"The greatest goodfor the greatest number."With this basic principleof utility on hand,let's begin to test itand to examine itby turning to another case,another story, but this time,not a hypothetical story,a real life story,the case of the Queenversus Dudley and was a th centuryBritish law casethat's famous and much debatedin law 's what happened in the 'll summarize the storythen I want to hearhow you would rule,imagining that you were the newspaper account of the timedescribed the sadder story of disasterat sea was never toldthan that of the survivorsof the yacht, ship flounderedin the South Atlantic, miles from the were four in the crew,Dudley was the captain,Stevens was the first mate,Brooks was a sailor,all men of excellent characteror so the newspaper account tells fourth crew memberwas the cabin boy,Richard Parker, years was an orphan,he had no family,and he was on his firstlong voyage at went,the news account tells us,rather against the adviceof his went in the hopefulnessof youthful ambition,thinking the journeywould make a man of , it was not to facts of the casewere not in wave hit the shipand the Mignonette went four crew membersescaped to a only food they hadwere two cans ofpreserved turnips,no fresh the first three days,they ate the fourth day,they opened oneof the cans of turnipsand ate next daythey caught a with the othercan of turnips,the turtle enabled themto subsist for the next few then for eight days,theyhad food. No yourselfin a situation like that,what would you doHere's what they now the cabin boy, Parker,is lying at the bottomof the lifeboatin the cornerbecause he had drunk seawateragainst the advice of the othersand he had become illand he appeared to be on the th day,Dudley, the captain,suggested that they should allhave a lottery,that they should draw lotsto see who would dieto save the didn't like the lottery don't knowwhether this wasbecause he didn't wantto take the chanceor because he believedin categorical moral in any case,no lots were next daythere was still no ship in sightso Dudley told Brooksto avert his gazeand he motioned to Stevensthat the boy, Parker,had better be offered a prayer,he told the boy his time had come,and he killed himwith a pen knife,stabbing himin the jugular emergedfrom his conscientious objectionto sharein the gruesome four days,the three of them fedon the body and bloodof the cabin then they were describes their rescuein his diary with staggering euphemism."On the th day,as we were having our breakfast,a ship appeared at last."The three survivorswere picked up by a German were taken backto Falmouth in Englandwhere they were arrestedand turned state's and Stevens went to didn't dispute the claimed they hadacted out of necessity;that was their argued in effectbetter that one should dieso that three could prosecutor wasn't swayedby that said murder is murder,and so the case went to imagine you are the just to simplify the discussion,put aside the question of law,let's assume that you as the juryare charged with decidingwhether what they didwas morally permissible or many would vote'not guilty',that what they didwas morally permissibleAnd how manywould vote 'guilty',what they did wasmorally wrongA pretty sizeable let's see what people's reasons areand let me begin with thosewho are in the 's hear first from the defenseof Dudley and would you morallyexonerate themWhat are your reasons think it is morallyreprehensiblebut I think thatthereis a distinctionbetween what's morally reprehensibleand what makes someonelegally other words,as the judge said,what's always moralisn't necessarily against the lawand while I don't thinkthat necessity justifies theftor murder or any illegal act,at some point your degreeof necessity does, in fact,exonerate you from any . Good. Other voices for the justificationsfor what they did. just feel likein the situation that desperate,you have to dowhat you have to do to have to dowhat you have to , you've got to dowhat you've got to you've been going days without any food, you know,someone just has to take the sacrifice,someone has to make the sacrificeand people can furthermore from that,let's say they surviveand then they become productivemembers of societywho go home and startlike a million charity organizationsand this and thatand this and mean they benefited everybodyin the end. , I mean I don't knowwhat they did afterwards,they might have gone and like,I don't know,killed more people, I don't but. -WhatMaybe they were if they went homeand they turned out to be assassinsWhat if they'd gone homeand turned out to be assassins Well…You'd want to knowwho they 's true too. That's 's fair. I would want to knowwho they right. That's 's your name. All 've heard a defense,a couple of voicesfor the we need to hearfrom the people thinkwhat they did was wrong. WhyYes. -One of the first thingsthat I was thinking wasthey haven't been eatingfor a really long timemaybe they're mentallylike affected and sothen that could be usedas a defense,a possible argumentthat they weren'tin the proper state of mind,they weren't making decisionsthey might otherwise be if that's an appealing argumentthat you have to bein an altered mindsetto do something like that,it suggests that peoplewho find that argument convincingdo think that they wereacting what do you-I want to knowwhat you defend 'm sorry, you vote to convict, rightYeah, I don't think thatthey acted in a morallyappropriate why notWhat do you say,here's Marcus,he justdefended said –you heard what he you've got to dowhat you've got to doin a case like that. do you say to MarcusThat there'sno situation that would allowhuman beings to take the ideaof fate orthe other people's livesin their own hands,that we don't havethat kind of . what's your name. Okay. Who elseWhat do you say Stand 'm wondering if Dudley and Stevenhad asked for Richard Parker'sconsent in you know, dying,if that would exonerate themfrom an act of murderand if so,is that still morally justifiableThat's right. wait, hang 's your name sayssuppose they had that,what would thatscenario look likeSo in the story Dudley is there,pen knife in hand,but instead of the prayeror before the prayer,he says "Parker, would you mind""We're desperately hungry",as Marcus empathizes with,"we're desperately 're not going to last long anyhow."-Yeah. You can be a martyr."Would you be a martyrHow about it Parker"Then what do you thinkWould it be morally justified thenSuppose Parkerin his semi-stupor says "Okay."I don't think it would bemorally justifiable but I'm wondering if –Even then, even then it wouldn't be don't think thateven with consentit would be morally justifiedAre there people who thinkwho want to take upKathleen's consent ideaand who think thatthat would make itmorally justifiedRaise your handif it would, if you think it 's very would consentmake a moral differenceWhy would it , I just thinkthat if he was makinghis own original ideaand it was his ideato start with,then that would bethe only situationin which I would see itbeing appropriate in any waybecause that wayyou couldn't make the argumentthat he was pressured,you know it's three-to-oneor whatever the ratio . -And I think that if he wasmaking a decisionto give his lifeand he took on the agencyto sacrifice himselfwhich some peoplemight see as admirableand other people might disagreewith that if he came upwith the idea,that's the only kindof consent we could haveconfidence in morallythen it would be , it would be kind ofcoerced consentunder the circumstances,you thereanyone who thinksthat even the consent of Parkerwould not justify their killing himWho thinks that us why. Stand think that Parkerwould be killed with the hopethat the other crew memberswould be rescued so there's nodefinite reason thathe should be killedbecause you don't knowwhen they're going to get rescuedso if you kill him,it's killing him in vain,do you keep killing a crew memberuntil you're rescuedand then you're left with no onebecause someone's goingto die eventuallyWell, the moral logicof the situation seems to be that,that they would keep onpicking off the weakest maybe,one by one,until they were in this case, luckily,they were rescued when three at leastwere still , if Parker did give his consent,would it be all right,do you think or notNo, it still wouldn't be tell us whyit wouldn't be all of all, cannibalism,I believe, is morally incorrectso you shouldn't beeating human cannibalism is morallyobjectionable as such so then,even on the scenario ofwaiting until someone died,still it would be , to me personally,I feel like it all dependson one's personal moralsand like we can't sit here and just,like this is just my opinion,of course other peopleare going to disagree, but –Well we'll see,let's see what their disagreements areand then we'll seeif they have reasons that canpersuade you or 's try that. All , is there someonewho can explain,those of you who aretempted by consent,can you explain whyconsent makes sucha moral differenceWhat about the lottery ideaDoes that count as consentRemember at the beginning,Dudley proposed a lottery,suppose that they had agreedto a lottery,then how many would then sayit was all rightSuppose there were a lottery,cabin boy lost,and the rest of the story unfolded,then how many people would sayit was morally permissibleSo the numbers are risingif we had a 's hear from one of youfor whom the lotterywould make a moral would itI think the essential element,in my mind,that makes it a crimeis the idea that they decidedat some point that their liveswere more important than his,andthat, I mean, that's kind ofthe basis for really any It's like my needs,my desires are more importantthan yours and minetake if they had done a lotterywhere everyone consentedthat someone should dieand it's sort of like they're allsacrificing themselvesto save the it would be all rightA little grotesque but–.-But morally permissible what's your name Matt, for you,what bothers you isnot the cannibalismbut the lack of due guess you could say And can someone who agreeswith Matt say a little bit moreabout why a lottery would make it,in your view, morally way I understood itoriginally was thatthat was the whole issueis that the cabin boywas never consultedabout whether or notsomething was goingto happen to him,even with the original lotterywhether or nothe would bea part of that,it was just decidedthat he was the onethat was going to , that's what happenedin the actual if there were a lotteryand they'd all agreed to the procedure,you think that would be okayRight, because then everyoneknows that there's going to be a death,whereas the cabin boy didn't know thatthis discussion was even happening,there was no forewarningfor him to know that"Hey, I may be the one that's dying."All , suppose everyone agreesto the lottery, they have the lottery,the cabin boy loses,and he changes his 've already decided,it's like a verbal can't go back on that,you've decided,the decision was you know that you're dyingfor the reason of others to someone else had died,you know that you wouldconsume them so –Right. But then you could say,"I know, but I lost".I just think thatthat's the whole moral issueis that there was no consultingof the cabin boyand that's what makes itthe most horribleis that he had no ideawhat was even going had he knownwhat was going on,it would be a bit right. I want to hear –so there are some who thinkit's morally permissiblebut only about %,led by there are some who saythe real problem hereis the lack of consent,whether the lack of consentto a lottery, to a fair procedure or,Kathleen's idea,lack of。
什么是公正_品读_公正_该如何做是好_陈雪茹

THE CHINESE PROCURATORS《公正———该如何做是好?》这本书源于哈佛大学教授迈克尔.桑德尔的公开课《论公正》。
迈克尔·桑德尔教授在书中探讨了“什么是公正”这个古老又永远年轻的话题。
“让我们从一个故事讲起。
”这是桑德尔第一堂课的第一句话。
他为这门课程设计、搜集了几十个故事和案例。
这些故事和案例绝不是噱头或花絮,而是激发学生思想的起点———请看他的故事如何展开:假设你是一个有轨电车司机,你的电车正以每小时六十英里的速度疾驶。
忽然,你看到前面轨道上,有五位工人在工作。
你想停下电车,但刹车坏了。
你感到绝望,电车正在向五位工人撞去,他们必死无疑。
就在这个时候,你发现轨道右边连接着另一根轨道,那根轨道的尽头,也有一位工人在工作。
电车的刹车坏了,可是方向盘没有失灵。
你可以把电车开上右边的轨道,前面轨道上的五位工人可以躲过一劫,但右边轨道上的那位工人却会被撞死。
第一个故事结束了。
桑德尔问:现在我们怎么做才是对的请大家举手,有多少人同意电车转向有多少人不同意?再从这个例子引申开去,假如面对失控的电车,你是一个在桥上看风景的旁观者,你发现电车即将撞向五个工人,你感到自己无能无力去避免这场灾难。
正在此时,你突然发现,你身边站着一个身材及其肥胖的人,你可以将他推下桥,落入轨道,从而挡住疾驰而来的电车。
他可能会被撞死,但是那五名工人却将获救。
(当然,你也考虑过自己跳下轨道,可你意识到自己身形太小了,恐怕无法挡住电车。
)你是否会将那个胖子推下桥这是否是正当之举?这里便产生了一个道德的难题,为什么牺牲一个生命以挽救另外五个生命,在第一种情形看起来似乎是正确的,而在第二种情形看起来却是让人难以接受,甚至是错误的呢?这个是《公正———该如何做是好?》这本书中的一个例子,而这样的引人深思的例子在书中比比皆是。
关于公开课。
迈克尔.桑德尔教授在哈佛讲授这门课已经30多年了,从最初的只能容纳15人的一个小教室,讲到了哈佛的“地标”———桑德斯剧场。
- 1、下载文档前请自行甄别文档内容的完整性,平台不提供额外的编辑、内容补充、找答案等附加服务。
- 2、"仅部分预览"的文档,不可在线预览部分如存在完整性等问题,可反馈申请退款(可完整预览的文档不适用该条件!)。
- 3、如文档侵犯您的权益,请联系客服反馈,我们会尽快为您处理(人工客服工作时间:9:00-18:30)。
This is a course about justice and we begin with a story. Suppose you're the driver of a trolley car, and your trolley car is hurtling down the track at 60 miles an hour. And at the end of the track, you notice five workers working on the track. You try to stop but you can't, your brakes don't work. You feel desperate becauseyou know that if you crash into thesefive workers, they will all die. Let's assume you know that for sure. And so you feel helpless until you notice that there is, off to the right, a side track and at the end of that track, there is one worker working on the track. Your steering wheel works, so you can turn the trolley car, if you want to, onto the side track killing the one but sparing the five. Here's our first question: what's the right thing to do? What would you do? Let's take a poll. How many would turn the trolley car onto the side track? Raise your hands. How many wouldn't? How many would go straight ahead?Keep your hands up those of you who would go straight ahead. A handful of people would, the vast majority would turn. Let's hear first, now we need to begin to investigate the reasons why you think it's the right thing to do.Let's begin with those in the majority who would turn to go onto the side track. Why would you do it? What would be your reason? Who's willing to volunteer a reason? Go ahead. Stand up. Because it can't be right to kill five people when you can only kill one person instead. It wouldn't be right to kill five if you could kill one person instead. That's a good reason. Who else? Does everybody agree with that reason?Go ahead. Well I was thinkingit's the same reason on 9/11 with regard to the people who flew the plane into the Pennsylvania field as heroes becausethey chose to kill the people on the plane and not kill more people in big buildings. So the principle there was the same on 9/11. It's a tragic circumstance but better to kill one so that five can live, is that the reason most of you had, those of you who would turn? Yes? Let's hear now from those in the minority, those who wouldn't turn. Yes. Well, I think that's the sametype of mentality that justifies genocide and totalitarianism. In order to save one type of race, you wipe out the other. So what would you do in this case?You would, to avoid the horrors of genocide, you would crash into the five and kill them? Presumably, yes. You would?-Yeah. Okay. Who else? That's a brave answer. Thank you.Let's consider another trolley car case and seewhether those of you in the majority want to adhere to the principle: "better that one should die so that five should live." This time you're not the driver of the trolley car, you're an onlooker. You're standing on a bridge overlooking a trolley car track. And down the track comes a trolley car, at the end of the track are five workers, the brakes don't work, the trolley car is about to careen into the five and kill them. And now, you're not the driver, you reallyfeel helpless until you notice standing next to you, leaning over the bridge is a very fat man. And you could give him a shove. He would fall over the bridge onto the track right in the way of the trolley car. Hewould die but he would spare the five. Now, how many would push the fat man over the bridge? Raise your hand. How many wouldn't? Most people wouldn't. Here's the obvious question. What becameof the principle "better to savefive lives even if it meanssacrificing one?" What becameof theprinciple that almost everyone endorsed in the first case? I need to hear from someone who was in the majority in both cases. How do you explain the difference between the two? Yes. The second one, I guess,involves an active choice of pushing a person down which I guess that person himself would otherwise not have been involved in the situation at all. And so to choose on his behalf, I guess, to involve him in something that he otherwise would have escapedis, I guess, more than what you have in the first case where the three parties, the driver and the two sets of workers, are already, I guess, in the situation. But the guy working, the one on the track off to the side, he didn't choose to sacrifice his life any more than the fat man did, did he? That's true, but he was on the tracks and... This guy was on the bridge. Go ahead, you can come back if you want. All right. It's a hard question. You did well. You did very well. It's a hard question. Who else can find a way of reconciling the reaction of the majority in these two cases?Yes. Well, I guess in the first case where you have the one worker and the five, it's a choice between those two and you have to make acertain choice and people are going to die becauseof the trolley car, not necessarily becauseof your direct actions. The trolley car is a runawaything and you're making a split second choice. Whereas pushing the fat man over is an actual act of murder on your part. You have control over that whereas you may not have control over the trolley car. So I think it's a slightly different situation. All right, who has a reply? That's good. Who has a way? Who wants to reply? Is that a way out of this? I don't thinkthat's a very good reason because you choose to- either way you have to choose who dies becauseyou either choose to turn and kill the person, which is an act of conscious thought to turn, or you choose to push the fat man over which is also an active, conscious action. So either way, you're making a choice. Do you want to reply? rm not really sure that that's the case. It just still seems kind of different. The act of actually pushing someone over onto the tracks and killing him, you are actually killing him yourself. You're pushing him with your own hands.You're pushing him andthat's different than steering something that is going to cause death into another. You know, it doesn't really sound right saying it now.No, no. It's good. It's good.What's your name? Andrew. Andrew. Let me ask you this question, Andrew. Yes. Suppose standing on the bridge next to the fat man, I didn't have to push him, supposehe was standing over a trap door that I could open by turning a steering wheel like that. Would you turn? For some reason, that still just seems more wrong. Right? I mean, maybe if you accidentally like leaned into the steering wheel or something like that. But... Or say that the car is hurtling towards a switch thatwill drop the trap. Then I could agree with that. That's all right. Fair enough. It still seemswrong in away that it doesn't seem wrong in the first case to turn, you say. And in another way, I mean, in the first situation you're involved directly with the situation. In the secondone, you're an onlooker as well. All right. -So you have the choice of becoming involved or not by pushing the fat man. All right. Let's forget for the moment about this case.That's good. Let's imagine a different case. This time you're a doctor in an emergency room and six patients come to you. They've been in a terrible trolley car wreck.Five of them sustain moderate injuries,one is severely injured, you could spend all day caring for the one severely injured victim but in that time, the five would die. Or you could look after the five, restore them to health but during that time, the one severely injured person would die. How many would save the five? Now as the doctor, how many would save the one? Very few people, just a handful of people. Same reason, I assume.Onelife versus five?Now consider another doctor case. This time, you're a transplant surgeon and you have five patients, each in desperate need of an organ transplant in order to survive.One needs a heart, one a lung, one a kidney,one a liver, and the fifth a pancreas.And you have no organdonors.You are about to see them die.And then it occurs to you that in the next room there's a healthy guy who came in for a check-up. And he's -youlike that -and he's taking a nap, you could go in very quietly,yank out the five organs, that person would die, but you could save the five. How many would do it?Anyone? How many? Put your handsup if you would do it.Anyone in the balcony?I would.You would? Be careful,don't lean over too much. How manywouldn't?All right. What do you say? Speak up in the balcony, you who would yank out the organs. Why? rd actually like to explore a slightly alternate possibility of just taking the one of the five who needsan organ who dies first and using their four healthy organs to save the other four. That's a pretty good idea. That's a great idea except for the fact that you just wrecked the philosophical point.Let's step back from these stories and these arguments to notice a couple of things about the way the arguments have begun to unfold. Certain moral principles have already begun to emerge from the discussions we've had. And let's consider what those moral principles look like. The first moral principle that emerged in the discussion said the right thing to do, the moral thing to do depends on the consequences that will result from your action. At the end of the day, better that five should live even if one must die. That's an example of consequentialist moral reasoning. Consequentialist moral reasoning locates morality in the consequencesof an act, in the state of the world that will result from the thing you do. But then we went alittle further, we considered those other cases and people weren't so sure about consequentialist moral reasoning. When people hesitated to push the fat man over the bridge or to yank out the organs of the innocent patient, people gestured toward reasons having to do with the intrinsic quality of the act itself, consequencesbe what they may.People were reluctant. People thought it was just wrong, categorically wrong, to kill a person, an innocent person, even for the sake of saving five lives. At least people thought that in the secondversion of each story we considered. So this points to a second categorical way of thinking about moral reasoning.Categorical moral reasoning locates morality in certain absolute moral requirements, certain categorical duties and rights, regardless of the consequences. We're going to explore in the days and weeks to come the contrast between consequentialist and categorical moral principles. The most influential example of consequential moral reasoning is utilitarianism, a doctrine invented by Jeremy Bentham, the 18th century English political philosopher. The most important philosopher of categorical moral reasoning is the 18th century German philosopher Immanuel Kant. So we will look at those two different modes of moral reasoning, assessthem, and also consider others. If you look at the syllabus, you'll notice that we read a number of great and famous books, books by Aristotle, John Locke, Immanuel Kant, John Stewart Mill, and others. You'll notice too from the syllabus sthat we don't only read these books; we also take up contemporary,political, and legal controversies that raise philosophical questions. We will debate equality and inequality, affirmative action, free speech versus hate speech,samesex marriage, military conscription, a range of practical questions. Why? Not just to enliven these abstract and distant books but to make clear, to bring out what's at stake in our everyday lives, including our political lives, for philosophy. And so we will read these books and we will debatethese issues, and we'll see how each informs and illuminates the other. This may sound appealing enough, but here I have to issue a warning. And the warning is this,to read these books in this way as an exercise in self knowledge, to read them in this way carries certain risks, risks that are both personal and political, risks that every student of political philosophy has known. These risks spring from the fact that philosophy teachesus and unsettles us by confronting us with what we already know. There's an irony.The difficulty of this course consists in the fact that it teaches what you already know. It works by taking what we know from familiar unquestioned settings and making it strange. That's how those examples worked, the hypothetical with which we began, with their mix of playfulness and sobriety. It's also how these philosophical books work. Philosophy estranges us from the familiar, not by supplying new information but by inviting and provoking a new way of seeing but, and here's the risk, once the familiar turns strange, it's never quite the same again. Self knowledgeis like lost innocence, however unsettling you find it; it can never be un-thought or un-known. What makes this enterprise difficult but also riveting is that moral and political philosophy is a story and you don't know where the story will lead. But what you do know is that the story is about you. Those are the personal risks. Now what of the political risks? One way of introducing a course like this would be to promise you that by reading these books and debating these issues, you will become a better, more responsible citizen; you will examine the presuppositions of public policy, you will hone your political judgment, you will become a more effective participant in public affairs. But this would be a partial and misleading promise. Political philosophy, for the most part, hasn't worked that way. You have to allow for the possibility that political philosophy may make you a worse citizen rather than a better one or at least a worse citizen before it makes you a better one, and that's becausephilosophy is a distancing, even debilitating, activity. And you see this, going back to Socrates, there's a dialogue, the Gorgias, in which one of Socrates' friends, Callicles, tries to talk him out of Philosophizing. Calliclestells Socrates "Philosophy is a pretty toy if one indulges in it with moderation at the right time of life. But if one pursues it further than one should, it is absolute ruin." "Take my advice," Callicles says, "abandon argument. Learn the accomplishments of active life, take for your models not those people who spend their time on these petty quibbles butthose who have a good livelihood and reputation and many other blessings." So Callicles is really saying to Socrates "Quit philosophizing, get real, go to business school." And Callicles did have a point. He had a point because philosophy distances us from conventions, from established assumptions, and from settled beliefs. Those are the risks, personal and political. And in the face of these risks, there is a characteristic evasion. The name of the evasion is skepticism, it's the idea —well, it goes something like this —we didn't resolve once and for all either the cases or the principles we were arguing when we began and if Aristotle and Locke and Kant and Mill haven't solved these questions after all of these years, who are we to think that we, here in Sanders Theatre, over the course of a semester,can resolve them? And so, maybe it's just a matter of each person having his or her own principles and there's nothing more to be said about it, no way of reasoning. That's the evasion, the evasion of skepticism, to which I would offer the following reply. It's true, these questions have been debated for a very long time but the very fact that they have recurred and persisted may suggest that though they're impossible in one sense,they're unavoidable in another. And the reasonthey're unavoidable, the reason they're inescapable is that we live some answer to these questions every day. So skepticism, just throwing up your handsand giving up on moral reflection is no solution. Immanuel Kant described very well the problem with skepticism when he wrote "Skepticism is a restingplace for human reason, where it can reflect upon its dogmatic wanderings, but it is no dwelling place for permanent settlement." "Simply to acquiesce in skepticism," Kant wrote, "can never suffice to overcome the restlessnessof reason." rve tried to suggestthrough these stories and these arguments some sense of the risks and temptations, of the perils and the possibilities. I would simply conclude by saying that the aim of this course is to awaken the restlessnessof reason and to see where it might lead. Thank you very much. Like, in a situation that desperate,you have to do what you have to do to survive.- You have to do what you have to do? You got to do what you got to do, pretty much. If you've been going 19 days without any food, you know, someonejust hasto take the sacrifice. Someone has to make the sacrifice and people can survive. Alright, that's good. What's your name? Marcus. -Marcus, what do you say to Marcus? Last time, we started out last time with some stories, with some moral dilemmas about trolley cars and about doctors and healthy patients vulnerable to being victims of organ transplantation. We noticed two things about the arguments we had, one had to do with the way we were arguing. We began with our judgments in particular cases.We tried to articulate the reasons or the principles lying behind our judgments. And then confronted with a new case, we found ourselves reexamining those principles, revising each in the light of the other. And we noticed the built in pressure to try to bring into alignment our judgments about particular cases and the principles we wouldendorse on reflection. We also noticed something about the substance of the arguments that emerged from the discussion. We noticed that sometimes we were tempted to locate the morality of an act in the consequences,in the results, in the state of the world that it brought about. And we calledthis consequentialist moral reasoning. But we also noticed that in some cases, we weren't swayed only by the result. Sometimes, many of us felt, that not just consequencesbut also the intrinsic quality or character of the act matters morally. Some people argued that there are certain thing that are just categorically wrong even if they bring about a good result, even if they saved five people at the cost of one life. So we contrasted consequentialist moral principles with categorical ones. Today and in the next few days, we will begin to examine one of the most influential versions of consequentialist moral theory. And that's the philosophy of utilitarianism. Jeremy Bentham, the 18th century English political philosopher gave first the first clear systematic expression to the utilitarian moral theory. And Bentham's idea, his essential idea, is a very simple one. With a lot of morally intuitive appeal, Bentham's idea is the following, the right thing to do; the just thing to do is to maximize utility. What did he mean by utility? He meant by utility the balance of pleasure over pain, happiness over suffering. Here's how he arrived at the principle of maximizing utility. He started out by observing that all of us, all human beings are governed by two sovereign masters: pain andpleasure. We human beings like pleasure and dislike pain. And so we should base morality, whether we're thinking about what to do in our own lives or whether as legislators or citizens, we're thinking about what the laws should be. The right thing to do individually or collectively is to maximize, act in away that maximizes the overall level of happiness. Bentham's utilitarianism is sometimes summed up with the slogan "The greatest good for the greatest number." With this basic principle ofutility on hand, let's begin to test it and to examine it by turning to another case, another story, but this time, not a hypothetical story, a real life story, the case of the Queen versus Dudley and Stevens. This was a 19th century British law case that's famous and much debated in law schools. Here's what happenedin the case.I'll summarize the story then I want to hear how you would rule, imagining that you were the jury. A newspaper account of the time described the background. A sadder story of disaster at sea was never told than that of the survivors of the yacht, Mignonette. The ship floundered in the South Atlantic, 1300 miles from the cape. There were four in the crew, Dudley was the captain, Stevens was the first mate, Brooks was a sailor, all men of excellent character or so the newspaper account tells us. The fourth crew member was the cabin boy, Richard Parker, 17 years old. He was an orphan, he had no family, and he was on his first long voyage at sea. He went, the news account tells us, rather against the advice of his friends. He went in the hopefulness ofyouthful ambition, thinking the journey would make a man of him. Sadly, itwas not to be. The facts of the case were not in dispute. A wave hit the ship and the Mignonette went down. The four crew members escapedto a lifeboat. The only food they had were two cans of preserved turnips, no fresh water. For the first three days, they ate nothing. On the fourth day, they opened one of the cans of turnips and ate it. The next day they caught a turtle. Together with the other can of turnips, the turtle enabled them to subsist for the next few days. And then for eight days, they had nothing. No food. No water. Imagine yourself in a situation like that, what would you do? Here's what they did. By now the cabin boy, Parker, is lying at the bottom of the lifeboat in the corner becausehe had drunk seawater against the advice of the others and he had become ill and he appeared to be dying. So on the 19th day, Dudley, the captain, suggested that they should all have a lottery, that they should draw lots to see who would die to save the rest. Brooks refused. He didn't like the lottery idea. We don't knowwhether this was because he didn't want to take the chance or becausehebelieved in categorical moral principles. But in anycase, no lots were drawn. The next day there was still no ship in sight so Dudley told Brooks to avert his gaze and he motioned to Stevens that the boy, Parker, had better be killed. Dudley offered a prayer, he told the boy his time had come, and he killed him with a pen knife, stabbing him in the jugular vein. Brooks emerged from his conscientious objection to share in the gruesome bounty. For four days, the three of them fed on the body and blood of the cabin boy. True story. And then they were rescued. Dudley describes their rescue in his diary with staggering euphemism. "On the 24th day, aswe were having our breakfast, a ship appeared at last." The threesurvivors were picked up by a German ship. They were taken back to Falmouth in England where they were arrested and tried. Brooks turned state's witness. Dudley and Stevens went to trial. They didn't dispute the facts. They claimed they had acted out of necessity; that was their defense. They argued in effect better that one should die so that three could survive. The prosecutor wasn't swayed by that argument. He said murder is murder, and so the case went to trial. Now imagine you are the jury. And just to simplify the discussion, put aside the question of law, let's assume that you as the jury are charged with deciding whether what they did was morally permissible or not. How many would vote 'not guilty', that what they did was morally permissible? And how many would vote 'guilty', what they did was morally wrong? A pretty sizeable majority. Now let's see what people's reasonsare and let me begin with those who are in the minority. Let's hear first from the defense of Dudley and Stevens. Why would you morally exoneratethem? What are your reasons?Yes. I think it is morally Reprehensible but I think that there is a distinction between what's morally reprehensible and what makes someone legally accountable. In other words, as the judge said, what's always moral isn't necessarily against the law and while I don't think that necessity justifies theft or murder or any illegal act, at some point your degree of necessity does, in fact, exonerate you from any guilt. Okay. Good. Other defenders. Other voices for the defense. Moral justificationsfor what they did. Yes. Thank you. I just feel like in the situation that desperate,you have to do You have to do what you have to do. Yeah, you've got to do what you've got to do Pretty much. If you've been going 19 days without any food, you know, someonejust has to take the sacrifice, someone has to make the sacrifice and people can survive. And furthermore from that, let's say they survive and then they become productive members of society who go home and startlike a million charity organizations and this and that and this and that. I mean they benefited everybody in the end. -Yeah So, I mean I don't know what they did afterwards, they might have gone and like, I don't know, killed more people, I don't know. Whatever but. -What? Maybe they were assassins.What if they went home and they turned out to be assassins?Whatif they'd gone home and turned out to be assassins?Well …You'd want to know who they assassinated. That's true too. That's fair. That's fair. I would want to know who they assassinated.All right. That's good.What's your name? Marcus. Marcus. All right. We've heard a defense, a couple of voices for the defense. Now we need to hear from the prosecution. Most people think what they did was wrong. Why? Yes. -One of the first things that I was thinking was they haven't been eating for a really long time maybe they're mentally like affected and so then that could be used as a defense,a possible argument that they weren't in the proper state of mind, they weren't making decisions they might otherwise be making. And if that's an appealing argumentthat you have to be in an altered mindset to do something like that, it suggests that people who find that argument convincing do think that they were acting immorally. But what do you- I want to know what you think. You defend them. I'm sorry, you vote to convict, right? Yeah, I don't thinkthat they acted in a morally appropriate way. And why not? What do you say, here's Marcus, he just defended them. He said - you heard what he said. Yes. That you've got to do what you've got to do in a case like that. -Yeah. -What do you say to Marcus? That there's no situation that would allow human beings to take the idea of fate or the other people's lives in their own hands, that we don't have that kind of power. Good. Okay. Thank you. And what's your name?Britt. Britt. Okay. Who else?What do you say?Stand up. rm wondering if Dudley and Steven had asked for Richard Parker's consent in you know, dying, if that would exonerate them from an act of murder and if so, is that still morally justifiable? That's interesting.All right. Consent. Wait wait, hang on. What's your name? Kathleen. Kathleen says suppose they had that, what would that scenario look like? So in the story Dudley is there, pen knife in hand, but instead of the prayer or before the prayer, he says "Parker, would you mind?" "We're desperately hungry", as Marcus empathizes with, "we're desperately hungry. You're not going to last long anyhow."- Yeah. You can be a martyr. "Would you be a martyr? How about it Parker?" Then what do you think? Would it be morally justified then? Suppose Parker in his semi-stupor says "Okay." I don't think it would be morally justifiable but rm wondering if —ven then, even then it wouldn't be? -No. You don't think that even with consent it would be morally justified? Are there people who think who want to take up Kathleen's consent idea and who think that that would make it morally justified? Raise your hand if it would, if you think it would. That's very interesting. Why would consent make a moral difference? Why would it? Yes. Well, I just think that if he was making his own original idea and it was his idea to start with, then that would be the only situation in which I would see it being appropriate in any way because that way you couldn't make the argument that he was pressured, you know it's three-to-one or whatever the ratio was. Right. -And I think that if he was making a。